Authors: Alfie Kohn
The most thoroughly documented example of how cooperation is a more effective means to personal gainâand how working at crosspurposes has the paradoxical effect of hurting everyoneâcomes from the Prisoner's Dilemma (PD) game that is so popular among psychologists (see footnote on
[>]
). Each of two playersâyou and anotherâsimultaneously chooses to “cooperate” or “defect,” and your decisions, taken together, determine the reward:
Â
Both cooperate: | You cooperate; the other defects: |
  You: 3 |   You: o |
  Other: 3 |   Other: 5 |
You defect; the other cooperates: | Both defect: |
  You: 5 |   You: 1 |
  Other: o |   Other: 1 |
Â
Here is the intriguing part: If the other person has defected, your losses will be cut if you defect, too. On the other hand, if the other person has cooperated, you can maximize your gain by defecting. From a strictly individual perspective, then, it seems rational to defect in either case. But seen as a unit, the two players do best when both cooperate. In the long run,
each
player does best when both cooperate. The game is somewhat contrived, of course, but its point is readily applicable to real life. Many of us pursue strategies that appear to be productive just so long as our standard remains what is in our own immediate best interest. When our perspective is widened we can see how this strategy is self-defeating to the community and, ultimately, even to ourselves.
Political scientist Robert Axelrod used the PD game to help determine whether individual nations would do better by cooperating or competingâa question firmly rooted in conventional Western individualism. He invited game theorists to submit computer programs with PD strategies; each program was then matched against all the others. The most successful entry
(TIT FOR TAT)
was the one that began by cooperating and then simply reciprocated the opponent's last move. A second tournament elicited more devious strategies, many of which included frequent defections, but
TIT FOR TAT
won again. Axelrod notes that this program “succeed[ed] by eliciting cooperation from others, not by defeating them,” and he concludes that “cooperation based on reciprocity can get started in a predominantly noncooperative world, can thrive in a variegated environment, and can defend itself once fully established.”
86
He stresses that people (or nations) are most apt to cooperate when they are relatively likely to have to deal with each other again in the future. (Other research with PD demonstrates that players do betterâthat is, cooperate more consistentlyâwhen they are given the chance to talk with each other beforehand.)
87
The first shift in perspectiveâfrom considering what benefits me to what benefits the groupâentails seeing most of Western political science and economics as fundamentally misconceived. Adam Smith asserted that when each person endeavored to further his or her best interests, each person gained. To someone who has rejected an individualist ethic, this proposition rests on a faulty assumptionânamely, the
a priori
belief that our analysis should be based on the solitary actor. The second, more moderate shift in perspectiveâwhich leaves our worldview similar to Smith's but offers a long-range viewâleads us to conclude that the prime theorist of capitalism was simply wrong. Everyone does
not
benefit when we struggle against each other for private gain. It is a simple matter of examining the evidence. To distinguish between what is rational for the individual and what is rational for the group is finally misleading because the former is
“not
rational, period. It is damaging not just to the group, but to the individual.”
88
But even this modest conclusion seems radical in light of our current zero-sum mentality. Having thoroughly assimilated the attitude that the better I do, the worse you do (and vice versa), we are not open to mutually advantageous agreement or cooperation of any kind. The costs can be high. The nightmarish problems now facing Mexico City, for example, are explained by its mayor as follows: “With our attitude in the past and perhaps also in the present, we have disordered this city because we have put individual interests before the collective interest.”
89
Similarly, although nuclear war benefits no one, some Americans take Soviet endorsement of any arms control agreement as sufficient reason to oppose it: if it's in their interest, it automatically must be against our interest. The enormous potential in mutual benefit (cooperative) strategies will not be tappedâor even understoodâuntil we broaden our perspective beyond the narrow prejudice that we always do best by trying to beat others.
Â
ECONOMIC COMPETITION
Â
In considering the social features of productivity, this chapter already has broached the matter of economic competition. This is a subject almost impossible to avoid in the course of exploring the effects of competition in our cultureâparticularly inasmuch as our economic system may well be the prototype of competition from which other varieties derive.
90
Capitalism can be thought of as the heart of competitiveness in American society.
Interestingly, most critics of capitalism are concerned not so much with the competitive basis of the system as with the fact that this competition is, in practice, unfair. Surely this criticism is well earned: it is a curious race indeed in which one competitor must try to scramble up from poverty while another starts out with a huge trust fund. A multinational corporation, similarly, has the capital and the tax advantages that allow it to trounceâor simply acquireâa small competitor. Once a business becomes large enough (e.g., Chrysler, Lockheed, Continental Bank), it simply cannot be allowed to fail. The result is that most sectors of the economy are becoming ever more concentrated, with a handful of concerns controlling the lion's share of business. Other profound inequities exist in an economy whose competition is so grossly unfairâor, to use the euphemism of choice, “imperfect.” More than half of the largest 250 corporations paid no taxes (or received rebates) in at least one of three years in the mid-1980s,
91
while forty to fifty million Americans live in poverty.
92
Despite the enormous discrepancy between perfect competition and the actual state of our economic system, competition is still the stated ideal. Businesspeople and public officials use the term as an honorific, discussing ways in which they can make their companies and countries “more competitive” and never pausing to ask whether a competitive system really is the best possible arrangement. Even progressive thinkers have come to identify true competition as the (rarely realized) ideal and cooperation, manifested as collusion, price fixing, and so on, as the salient evil.
When critics see things this way, they do not mean to repudiate genuine cooperation; they are simply accepting (often unconsciously) the premises and vocabulary of corporate capitalism. Within this framework, the word
cooperation
signifies little more than violation of antitrust laws. But critics of our economic system have, I think, made a serious mistake in accepting competition as a theoretical good and directing their energies to the question of how best to attain it. This not only has a stultifying effect on the discussion of economic issues; it spills over into other realms. Competition becomes generally identified as desirable and alternatives are regarded with suspicion when they are regarded at all. We need to develop a critique that will question the productiveness of competition itself and not simply assume that we are going about it in the wrong way. The following discussion will take this tack, although it will not provide anything like a comprehensive critique. It will simply raise a few questions about the value of a competitive economic system.
***
Economics is the study of how commodities are produced, distributed, and consumed. Most economists see their job as finding the most efficient means of satisfying demand for these commodities. Competition is justified on the grounds of its putative efficiency and, further, its usefulness at stimulating growth. The first question one could askâalthough in practice almost no one doesâis whether economic growth is always desirable. Paul Wachtel, in his book
The Poverty of Affluence,
shows how such growth entails significant costs to our health and safety, makes our working lives unhappy (for all we might gain in quality of life as consumers, we lose as producers), fails to bring about greater equity, and actually represents a desperate and futile attempt to compensate for psychological and social deficiencies.
93
But let us assume for the sake of the argument that producing more goods is a legitimate goal. Does a competitive system represent the best way to meet this goal? We have considerable reason to doubt that it does.
⢠   Working to maximize individual gain by competing against others can be counterproductive in the long run, as the last section suggested.
⢠   The evidence already reviewed from Robert Helmreich demonstrates that competitiveness does not make people more productiveâeven when productivity is measured by a businessman's earnings. Other data confirm that structural competition promotes achievement less well than cooperation in a variety of settings. The obvious question is why this should suddenly cease to be the case when we turn our attention to the economic system as a whole.
⢠   At least one study has found that competitive behavior appears more frequently and more vigorously on the part of children with lower socioeconomic origins.
94
We should be cautious in interpreting this finding: it may be that competition is a socialized response to poverty, an attempt (however misguided) to improve one's condition. Alternatively, it may reflect the fact that competition appears to be particularly stressed in lower-income schools.
95
But such a finding, considered alongside Helmreich's, suggests that competition may just be counterproductive.
⢠Margaret Mead's cross-cultural studies led her to conclude that cooperation is more effective than competition at maximizing production. A more recent review of the research forced Roderic Gorney to acknowledge that achievement on the part of a society did not depend on its competitiveness (see
[>]
).
The case for the desirability of economic competition is usually made as a result of assumptions about scarcity. Mead emphasizes that it is cultural norms and not objective scarcity that determine whether a society's economic system is competitive, but one could still argue that competition is the best arrangement for dealing with scarcity. The subject deserves attention.
By “scarcity,” most of us mean that goods are in short supply: there isn't enough of something to go around. While there often is no clear-cut understanding of what constitutes “enough,” the simple fact is that there is more than sufficient food to sustain everyone on the planet.
96
The same is true of land and renewable energy. The important question, then, is why the staples of life are so egregiously maldistributedâwhy, for example, the United States, with a little more than 5 percent of the world's population, uses something like 40 percent of the world's resources. What appears to be a problem of scarcity usually turns out, on closer inspection, to be a problem of distribution. But mainstream economists are notably unconcerned with distributional issues: they talk only about whether a given system is productive or efficient, and it is up to us to ask, “For
whom
?” A high gross national product tells us nothing about who has access to the goods; likewise, the absence of goods on the part of particular individuals or nations raises the question of whether someone else has a surfeit.
The point is this: if there is enough of the necessities to go around but they are not going around, the debate must shift to the impact of competition on matters of distribution. Can the inequities be blamed on competition itself? Even if not, the key question is whether more competition would rectify the situation. It is hard to imagine how it could. Whoever has more resources is far more likely to win a contest, thus giving her even more resources for the next contest, and so on until the opponent is utterly vanquished or someone steps in to stop the competition. Government regulations and income transfer mechanismsâwhich free-market apologists correctly identify as limitations on pure competitionâare all that prevent inequities even more pronounced than those now in existence. To take another kind of evidence, Gorney demonstrated a significant correlation between competition in a culture and the presence of sharply delineated “have” and “have-not” groups (see
[>]
). On whatever grounds competition might be defended, equity simply cannot be considered one of its benefits. Thus it would seem to be precisely the wrong strategy for dealing with the maldistribution of goods, which is perhaps the most critical economic reality to be addressed.
When economists talk about scarcity, however, they generally are not using the word to mean that goods are in short supply. Their technical use of the term refers instead to (1) the fact that choosing one commodity involves giving up the chance to have another, or (2) the presumed failure of people to be satisfied regardless of how much they have. Let us take these in turn.
The first usage defines a scarce good as one for which a consumer would give up something else. Scarcity, then, concerns the mutually exclusive relationship between commodities. This may be a useful way of looking at the world in some respects, but it tells us nothing about the absolute status of a given commodity. The model is set up so all finite goods will always be considered “scarce”; the availability of each is being evaluated vis-Ã -vis the others. By definition, no economic system can remedy this state of affairs, so competition is no more sensible a way to deal with scarcity than any other arrangement.