The Blind Watchmaker (54 page)

Read The Blind Watchmaker Online

Authors: Richard Dawkins

Tags: #Science, #Life Sciences, #Evolution, #General

At first glance this idea has a certain seductive plausibility, but only at a very brief first glance. The seductiveness comes from the neatly symmetrical way in which natural selection is turned on its head. Natural selection, in its most simple form, assumes that the environment is imposed upon the species, and those genetic variants best fitted to that environment survive. The environment is imposed, and the species evolves to fit it. Dover’s theory turns this on its head. It is the nature of the species that is ‘imposed’, in this case by the vicissitudes of mutation, and other internal genetic forces in which he has a special interest. The species then locates that member of the set of all environments that best fits its imposed nature.

But the seductiveness of the symmetry is superficial indeed. The wondrous cloud-cuckooism of Dover’s idea is displayed in all its glory the moment we begin to think in terms of numbers. The essence of his scheme is that, at each of the 1,000 steps, it didn’t matter which way the species turned. Each new innovation that the species came up with was functionally random, and the species then found an environment to suit it. The implication is that the species
would have found
a suitable environment, no matter which branch it had taken at every fork in the way. Now just think how many possible environments this lets us in for postulating. There were 1,000 branch points. If each branch point was a mere bifurcation (as opposed to a 3-way or 18-way branch, a conservative assumption), the total number of livable environments that must, in principle, exist, in order to allow Dover’s scheme to work, is 2 to the power 1,000 (the first branch gives two pathways; then each of those branches into two, making four in all; then each of these branches, giving 8, then 16, 32, 64,… all the way to 21‘000). This number may be written as a 1 with 301 noughts after it. It is far far greater than the total number of atoms in the entire universe.

Dover’s alleged rival to natural selection could never work, not just never in a million years but never in a million times longer than the universe has existed, never in a million universes each lasting a million times as long again. Notice that this conclusion is not materially affected if we change Dover’s initial assumption that 1,000 steps would be needed to make an eye. If we reduce it to only 100 steps, which is probably an underestimate, we still conclude that the set of possible livable environments that must be waiting in the wings, as it were, to cope with whatever random steps the lineage might take, is more than a million million million million million. This is a smaller number than the previous one, but it still means that the vast majority of Dover’s ‘environments’ waiting in the wings would each have to be made of less than a single atom.

It is worth explaining why the theory of natural selection is not susceptible to a symmetrical destruction by a version of the largenumbers argument’. In Chapter 3 we thought of all real and conceivable animals as sitting in a gigantic hyperspace. We are doing a similar thing here, but simplifying it by considering evolutionary branch points as 2-way, rather than 18-way branches. So the set of all possible animals that might have evolved in 1,000 evolutionary steps are perched on a gigantic tree, which branches and branches so that the total number of final twigs is 1 followed by 301 noughts. Any actual evolutionary history can be represented as a particular pathway through this hypothetical tree. Of all conceivable evolutionary pathways, only a minority actually ever happened. We can think of most of this ‘tree of all possible animals’ as hidden in the darkness of nonexistence. Here and there, a few trajectories through the darkened tree are illuminated. These are the evolutionary pathways that actually happened, and, numerous as these illuminated branches are, they are still an infinitesimal minority of the set of all branches. Natural selection is a process that is capable of picking its way through the tree of all conceivable animals, and finding just that minority of pathways that are viable. The theory of natural selection cannot be attacked by the kind of largenumbers argument with which I attacked Dover’s theory, because it is of the essence of the theory of natural selection that it is continually cutting down most of the branches of the tree. That is precisely what natural selection does. It picks its way, step by step, through the tree of all conceivable animals, avoiding the almost infinitely large majority of sterile branches - animals with eyes in the soles of their feet,
etc.
which the Dover theory is obliged, by the nature of its peculiar inverted logic, to countenance.

We have dealt with all the alleged alternatives to the theory of natural selection except the oldest one. This is the theory that life was created, or its evolution master-minded, by a conscious designer. It would obviously be unfairly easy to demolish some particular version of this theory such as the one (or it may be two) spelled out in Genesis. Nearly all peoples have developed their own creation myth, and the Genesis story is just the one that happened to have been adopted by one particular tribe of Middle Eastern herders. It has no more special Status than the belief of a particular West African tribe that the world was created from the excrement of ants. All these myths have in common that they depend upon the deliberate intentions of some kind of supernatural being.

At first sight there is an important distinction to be made between what might be called ‘instantaneous creation’ and ‘guided evolution’. Modern theologians of any sophistication have given up believing in instantaneous creation. The evidence for some sort of evolution has become too overwhelming. But many theologians who call themselves evolutionists, for instance the Bishop of Birmingham quoted in Chapter 2, smuggle Cod in by the back door: they allow him some sort of supervisory role over the course that evolution has taken, either influencing key moments in evolutionary history (especially, of course,
human
evolutionary history), or even meddling more comprehensively in the day-to-day events that add up to evolutionary change.

We cannot disprove beliefs like these, especially if it is assumed that God took care that his interventions always closely mimicked what would be expected from evolution by natural selection. All that we can say about such beliefs is, firstly, that they are superfluous and, secondly, that they
assume
the existence of the main thing we want to
explain
, namely organized complexity. The one thing that makes evolution such a neat theory is that it explains how organized complexity can arise out of primeval simplicity.

If we want to postulate a deity capable of engineering all the organized complexity in the world, either instantaneously or by guiding evolution, that deity must already have been vastly complex in the first place. The creationist, whether a naive Bible-thumper or an educated bishop, simply
postulates
an already existing being of prodigious intelligence and complexity. If we are going to allow ourselves the luxury of postulating organized complexity without offering an explanation, we might as well make a job of it and simply postulate the existence of life as we know it! In short, divine creation, whether instantaneous or in the form of guided evolution, joins the list of other theories we have considered in this chapter. All give some superficial appearance of being alternatives to Darwinism, whose merits might be tested by an appeal to evidence. All turn out, on closer inspection, not to be rivals of Darwinism at all. The theory of evolution by cumulative natural selection is the only theory we know of that is in principle
capable
of explaining the existence of organized complexity. Even if the evidence did not favour it, it would
still
be the best theory available! In fact the evidence does favour it. But that is another story.

Let us hear the conclusion of the whole matter. The essence of life is statistical improbability on a colossal scale. Whatever is the explanation for life, therefore, it cannot be chance. The true explanation for the existence of life must embody the very antithesis of chance. The antithesis of chance is nonrandom survival, properly understood. Nonrandom survival, improperly understood, is not the antithesis of chance, it is chance itself. There is a continuum connecting these two extremes, and it is the continuum from single-step selection to cumulative selection. Single-step selection is just another way of saying pure chance. This is what I mean by nonrandom survival improperly understood.
Cumulative selection
, by slow and gradual degrees, is the explanation, the only workable explanation that has ever been proposed, for the existence of life’s complex design.

The whole book has been dominated by the idea of chance, by the astronomically long odds against the spontaneous arising of order, complexity and apparent design. We have sought a way of taming chance, of drawing its fangs. ‘Untamed chance’, pure, naked chance, means ordered design springing into existence from nothing, in a single leap. It would be untamed chance if once there was no eye, and then, suddenly, in the twinkling of a generation, an eye appeared, fully fashioned, perfect and whole. This is possible, but the odds against it will keep us busy writing noughts till the end of time. The same applies to the odds against the spontaneous existence of any fully fashioned, perfect and whole beings, including - I see no way of avoiding the conclusion deities.

To ‘tame’ chance means to break down the very improbable into less improbable small components arranged in series. No matter how improbable it is that an X could have arisen from a Y in a single step, it is always possible to conceive of a series of infinitesimally graded intermediates between them. However improbable a largescale change may be, smaller changes are less improbable. And provided we postulate a sufficiently large series of sufficiently finely graded intermediates, we shall be able to derive anything from anything else, without invoking astronomical improbabilities. We are allowed to do this only if there has been sufficient time to fit all the intermediates in. And also only if there is a mechanism for guiding each step in some particular direction, otherwise the sequence of steps will career off in an endless random walk.

It is the contention of the Darwinian world-view that both these provisos are met, and that slow, gradual, cumulative natural selection is the ultimate explanation for our existence. If there are versions of the evolution theory that deny slow gradualism, and deny the central role of natural selection, they may be true in particular cases. But they cannot be the whole truth, for they deny the very heart of the evolution theory, which gives it the power to dissolve astronomical improbabilities and explain prodigies of apparent miracle.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

1. Alberts, B., Bray, D., Lewis, J., Raff, M., Roberts, K. & Watson, J.D. (1983)
Molecular Biology of the Cell
. New York: Garland.

2. Anderson, D.M. (1981) Role of interfacial water and water in thin films in the origin of life. In J.Billingham (ed.)
Life in the Universe
. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

3. Andersson, M. (1982) Female choice selects for extreme tail length in a widow bird. Nature, 299: 818-20.

4. Arnold, S.J. (1983) Sexual selection: the interface of theory and empiricism. In P.P.G.Bateson (ed.),
Mate Choice
, pp. 67-107. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

5. Asimov, 1. (1957)
Only a Trillion
. London: Abelard-Schuman.

6. Asimov, I. (1980)
Extraterrestrial Civilizations
. London: Pan.

7. Asimov, I. (1981)
In the Beginning
. London: New English Library.

8. Atkins, P.W. (1981)
The Creation
. Oxford: W.H.Freeman.

9. Attenborough, D. (1980)
Life on Earth
. London: Reader’s Digest, Collins &. BBC.

10. Barker, E. (1985) Let there be light: scientiri” creationism in the twentieth century. In J.R.Durant (ed.|
Darwinism and Divinity
, pp. 189-204. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

11. Bowler, P.J. (1984)
Evolution: the history of an idea
. Berkeley: University of California Press.

12. Bowles, K.L. (1977)
Problem-Solving using Pascal
. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

13. Cairns-Smith, A.G. (1982)
Genetic Takeover
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

14. Cairns-Smith, A.G. (1985)
Seven Clues to the Origin of Life
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

15. Cavalli-Sforza, L. & Feldman, M. (I981)
Cultural Transmission and Evolution
. Princeton, N.: Princeton University Press.

16. Cott, H.B. (1940)
Adaptive Coloration in Animals
. London: Methuen.

17. Crick, F. (1981)
Life Itself
. London: Macdonald.

18. Darwin, C. (1859)
The Origin of Species
. Reprinted. London: Penguin.

19. Dawkins, M.S. (1986)
Unravelling Animal Behaviour
. London: Longman.

20. Dawkins, R. (1976)
The Selfish Gene
. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

21. Dawkins, R. (1982)
The Extended Phenotype
. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

22. Dawkins, R. (1982) Universal Darwinism. In D.S.Bendall (ed.)
Evolution from Molecules to Men
, pp. 403-25. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

23. Dawkins, R. & Krebs, J.R. (1979) Arms races between and within Species.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London
, B, 205: 489-511.

24. Douglas, A.M. (1986) Tigers in Western Australia. New
Scientist
, 110 (1505): 44-7.

25. Dover, G.A. (1984) Improbable adaptations and Maynard Smith’s dilemma. Unpublished manuscript, and two public lectures, Oxford, 1984.

26. Dyson, F. (1985)
Origins of Life
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

27. Bigen, M., Gardiner, W., Schuster, P., & Winkler-Oswatitsch. (1981) The origin of genetic information.
Scientific American
, 244 (4): 88-118.’

28. Eisner, T. (1982) Spray aiming in bombardier beetles: jet deflection by the Coander Effect.
Science
, 215: 83-5.

29. Eldredge, N. (1985)
Time Frames: the rethinking of Darwinian evolution and the theory of punctuated equilibria
. New York: Simon & Schuster (includes reprinting of original Eldredge & Gould paper).

Other books

Rabbit, Run by John Updike
Lost by Francine Pascal
The Vengeance Man by Macrae, John
The Conqueror by Louis Shalako
Tell Me More by Janet Mullany
Judgment in Death by J. D. Robb
Zombie Ocean (Book 3): The Least by Grist, Michael John