Read The Outsider Online

Authors: Colin Wilson

The Outsider (16 page)

The importance of this passage cannot be overestimated. It shows Lawrence taking his stand in an extreme of Asiatic world-contempt, the antithesis of the modern Western spirit. Steppenwolf

s contempt for the bourgeois ideal reaches its logical end: anti-humanistic world-negation.

In another matter, Lawrence reinforces Steppenwolf

s conclusions: Haller

s recognition that he has not two, but many conflicting I

s.

Now I found myself dividing into parts.
...
The spent body toiled on doggedly and took no heed, quite rightly, for the divided selves said nothing I was not capable of thinking in cold blood ... they were all my natives. Telesius, taught by some such experience, split up the soul. Had he gone on to the furthest limit of exhaustion, he would have seen his conceived regiment of thoughts and acts and feelings ranked around him as separate creatures, eyeing, like vultures, the passing in their midst of the common thing that gave them life.
15

This capacity of Lawrence

s to bear physical pain is of central importance in understanding him. His clear-sighted intellect
could not conceive of moral freedom without physical freedom too; pain was an invaluable instrument in experiments to determine the extent of his moral freedom. His nihilism was fortified when he found himself unable to bear extremes, when, for instance, beaten by Turkish soldiers, the pain mastered his will not to cry out. Yet his conclusions point towards ultimate moral freedom:

During [our revolt] we often saw men push themselves or be driven to a cruel extreme of endurance, yet never was there an intimation of physical break. Collapse arose always from a moral weakness eating into the body, which of itself, without traitors from within, had no power over the Will.

While we rode we were disbodied, unconscious of flesh or feeling, and when, at an interval, this excitement faded and we did see our bodies, it was with some hostility, a contemptuous sense that they reached their highest purpose, not as vehicles of the spirit, but, when dissolved, their elements served to manure a field.
16

The will is supreme, but, as for Schopenhauer, it can exercise its ultimate freedom only by willing negation. Yet the belief in its fundamental importance gives us the key to Lawrence

s life; he had never ceased to experiment to test the power of his will:

Such liberties [abstaining from food and sleep] came from years of control (contempt of use might well be the lesson of our manhood) and they fitted me peculiarly for our work; but in me they came, half by training, half by trying
...
not effortlessly, as with the Arabs. Yet in compensation stood my energy of motive. Their less taut wills flagged before mine flagged, and by comparison made me seem tough and active.

There is, admittedly, a sort of contradiction involved in the two paragraphs quoted above. The Emersonian parenthesis,

Contempt of use might well be the lesson of our manhood

, follows logically from his earlier statement that

his senses
...
needed the immediacy of contact to achieve perception

. His asceticism is an attempt to

cleanse the doors of perception

(in Blake

s phrase). Yet this does not fit in with the earlier paragraph and its complete denial of the body. One line of thought leads to the conception that the body reaches its highest purpose with perfect

immediacy of perception achieved

, which is the conclusion of the mysticism of Boehme and Blake. The other leads to complete contempt, a cleansing of the senses that ultimately leads to throwing the senses away too.

Obviously, Lawrence

s metaphysics does not form a self-complete system, and where it shows contradictions, it does so because he never worked systematically at self-analysis. This particular contradiction is inherent in mysticism—the saint who sees all existence as holy, and the saint who is completely withdrawn from existence—and if Lawrence had ever empirically resolved it, the last fifteen years of his life might have been much easier to understand. The

mind suicide

of joining the R.A.F., and thereby involving himself with

the ignorant, the deceived, the superficial

, might have been rejected in favour of some less frustrating form of asceticism. Lawrence deliberately complicated the difficulty of self-realization by refusing to believe that he had any self to realize. He stated:

Indeed, the truth was I did not like the

myself

I could see and hear

,
17
but had no notion of how to proceed to unearth the self he
didn

t
dislike, the self he was aware of on that

clear dawn that woke up the senses with the sun, while the intellect
...
was yet abed

. Lawrence has all of the powers of a man who is capable of making tremendous efforts of will; he fails because he has no purpose towards which to direct the will. His failure is due to his inability to analyse the vague urges that stir in him, and bring them into the light of consciousness.

It is a curious fact that Granville-Barker sent Lawrence one of the first copies of
The Secret Life,
which he acknowledged reading in a letter of 7 February, 1924. There is no evidence that Lawrence saw a reflection of his own spiritual state in Evan Strowde or Oliver Gauntlett; he praises the play as being one of the best pictures of real politicians ever drawn! This is the disconcerting thing about Lawrence after the war; he seems to have given up the struggle. There is something about the abnegation of will of his R.A.F. years that is terribly like that paralysis of motive in the insanity of Nijinsky or Nietzsche. Stepp
e
nwolf has said,

There is no way back ... the
way lies on, ever further into guilt, ever deeper into human life.

But often a point of strain is reached where the Outsider cannot go on; the complications are too much. He asks for nothing but rest. Lawrence reached that point, and perhaps, in some ways, Steppenwolf

s ideal of cutting his throat would have been a more satisfactory conclusion than the

mind suicide

of the R.A.F. But there were still some things that had the power of exciting Lawrence to direct sensation, in spite of the

thought-riddled nature

, and one of these was speed. It was speed that eventually killed him, for he swerved his motor-bike to avoid two errand boys at the top of a hill, and crashed into a hedge at seventy miles an hour.

* * *

 

Lawrence

s work has introduced new implications into our study of

the Outsider

s problems

, and these can be seen most clearly by reviewing the ground covered so far. Lawrence has characteristics in common with all the Outsiders we have considered, and in him we can see the point to which some of them were tending.

From Barbusse, we can see that
the Outsider

s problem is the problem of denial of self expression.
This gave rise to the question of whether the Outsider is therefore a merely sociological problem. The introduction, in Wells

s pamphlet, of a definitely un-sociological aspect, led us naturally to Roquentin, where it was seen that the problem is, in fact, metaphysical.

Camus and Hemingway have emphasized its
practical
nature. It is a living problem; the problem of
pattern or purpose
in life. The Outsider is he who cannot accept life as it is, who cannot consider his own existence or anyone else

s
necessary.
He sees

too deep and too much

. It is still a question of self-expression.

In
The Secret Life
we see the Outsider cut off from other people by an intelligence that ruthlessly destroys their values, and prevents him from self-expression through his inability to substitute new values. His problem is Ecclesiastes


Vanitatum vanitas

; nothing is worth doing.

The romantic Outsider has broadened the approach by showing that it is not necessarily the problem of disillusioned men. On a different level, the romantic lives it in his striving to give flesh to the romantic ideal. Hesse

s conclusion was: more
self-analysis,

to traverse again the hell of the inner being
5
. The Outsider must know himself more. This involves Roquen-tin

s way and Meursault

s way; the way of metaphysical analysis and the way of acceptance of physical life. But the ultimate failure of both Goldmund and the Magister Ludi, the ways of flesh and spirit, leave us still faced with Strowde

s: Nothing is worth doing, no way is better than another.

It is Lawrence who has finally indicated the way out of this impasse. The others have accepted it as a problem in one variable, as it were. A

way
5
is to be sought. The question

A way
for whom*
would be answered by Roquentin or Strowde:

A way for me, obviously.
5
Lawrence has made the great step forward:

You are not what you think you are.

Instead of saying: Nothing is worth doing, you should say, 7 am not worth doing anything.
5
Oliver Gauntlett
5
s question of
where
the enemy is, has been answered by Lawrence:

You think he
is
you.
5
Oliver

s real war is a war against oneself. Lawrence has made the vital distinction in one sentence:

Indeed, I did not like the

myself
55
I could see and hear.
5

He is not himself
5
, Kennington
5
s schoolmaster had said. Lawrence does not divide himself up into two parts like Haller and then say

Man hates wolf
5
. It was a whole complex of body and mind and emotions that Lawrence hated, his ideas about himself that made a constant suffocating-blanket around his vital impulses.

This is a situation that is by no means unfamiliar to saints and mystics; Lawrence

s misfortune is in having so far found no biographer qualified to deal with his spiritual conflicts. The popular ideas of a

Lawrence enigma
5
have culminated in Mr. Aldington

s attempt to explain Lawrence in terms of Freud
5
s inadequate psychology. But the

Lawrence enigma
5
was cleared up by Lawrence himself in
The Seven Pillars.
Man is not a unity; he is many. But for anything to be worth doing, he must become a unity. The divided kingdom must be unified. The deluded vision of personality that our Western civilization fosters and glorifies, increases the inward division; Lawrence recognized it as the enemy. The war against it is therefore inevitably a revolt against Western civilization.

Lawrence

s achievement takes us even further. The war is not to be fought by mere reason. Reason leaves the personality comfortable on its own ground. The will

s power is immense when backed by moral purpose. Reason

s only role is to
establish moral purpose by self-analysis. Once the enemy is defined, the will can operate, and the limit of its power over the body is only the limit of moral purpose to back it.

If our reasoning is correct, the Outsider

s problem is not new; Lawrence points out that the history of prophets of all time follow a pattern: born in a civilization, they reject its standards of material well-being and retreat into the desert. When they return, it is to preach world rejection: intensity of spirit versus physical security. The Outsider

s miseries are the prophet

s teething pains. He retreats into his room, like a spider in a dark corner; he lives alone, wishes to avoid people.

To the thinkers of the desert, the impulse into Nitria had proved ever irresistible.

He thinks, he analyses, he

descends into himself:

Not that probably they found God dwelling there, but that in solitude they heard more certainly the living word they brought with them.

Gradually the message emerges. It need not be a positive massage; why should it, when the impulse that drives to it is negative—disgust?

Other books

Crush by Caitlin Daire
Letter to Belinda by Tim Tingle
The Official Patient's Sourcebook on Lupus by James N. Parker, MD, Philip M. Parker, PH.D
Aussie Grit by Mark Webber
Marcia's Madness by Lauren Baratz-Logsted