Chances Are

Read Chances Are Online

Authors: Michael Kaplan

Table of Contents
 
 
 
PENGUIN BOOKS
CHANCES ARE . . .
Michael Kaplan studied European history at Harvard and Oxford. After a stint as producer/director at WGBH, he has been an award-winning writer and filmmaker for corporations, governments, museums, and charities. He lives near Edinburgh, Scotland, with his wife and son.
 
Ellen Kaplan trained as a classical archaeologist and has taught math, biology, Greek, Latin, and history. She and her husband, Robert, run the Math Circle, a nonprofit foundation dedicated to joyous participatory learning, and are the authors of
The Art of the Infinite.
Michael Kaplan and Ellen Kaplan | Penguin Books
PENGUIN BOOKS
Published by the Penguin Group
Penguin Group (USA) Inc., 375 Hudson Street, New York, New York 10014, U.S.A. • Penguin
Group (Canada), 90 Eglinton Avenue East, Suite 700, Toronto, Ontario, Canada M4P 2Y3
(a division of Pearson Penguin Canada Inc.) • Penguin Books Ltd, 80 Strand, London WC2R 0RL,
England • Penguin Ireland, 25 St Stephen's Green, Dublin 2, Ireland (a division of Penguin Books
Ltd) • Penguin Group (Australia), 250 Camberwell Road, Camberwell, Victoria 3124, Australia
(a division of Pearson Australia Group Pty Ltd) • Penguin Books India Pvt Ltd, 11 Community
Centre, Panchsheel Park, New Delhi - 110 017, India • Penguin Group (NZ), 67 Apollo Drive,
Mairangi Bay, Auckland 1311, New Zealand (a division of Pearson New Zealand Ltd) • Penguin
Books (South Africa) (Pty) Ltd, 24 Sturdee Avenue, Rosebank, Johannesburg 2196, South Africa
 
Penguin Books Ltd, Registered Offices: 80 Strand, London WC2R 0RL, England
 
First published in the United States of America by Viking Penguin,
a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 2006
Published in Penguin Books 2007
 
 
Copyright © Michael Kaplan and Ellen Kaplan, 2006
All rights reserved
 
Grateful acknowledgment is made for permission
to reprint excerpts from the following copyrighted works:
“Law Like Love” from
Collected Poems
by W. H. Auden. Copyright 1940
and renewed 1968 by W. H. Auden. Used by permission of Random House, Inc.
“Choruses from ‘The Rock' ” from
Collected Poems 1909-1962
by T. S. Eliot.
Copyright 1936 by Harcourt, Inc. and renewed 1964 by T. S. Eliot. . and Faber and Faber Ltd.
“Hope” by Randall Jarrell. Copyright 1945 by Randall Jarrell, renewed 1990 by Mary von
Schrader Jarrell. .
 
eISBN : 978-1-440-68451-7
1. Probabilities—Popular works. I. Kaplan, Ellen. II. Title.
QA273.15.K37 2006
519.2—dc22 2005058471
 
 
 
The scanning, uploading and distribution of this book via the Internet or via any other means without the permission of the publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only authorized electronic editions, and do not participate in or encourage electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the author's rights is appreciated.

http://us.penguingroup.com

To Jane, who likes probability,
Bob, who likes chance,
and Felix, who likes risk
Acknowledgments
We live in wonderful times, where shared interests can make new friends instantly across the globe. We want most of all to thank the many people who agreed to be interviewed for this book, or who offered their particular expertise in person or by telephone, letter, or e-mail. We came to regard the enthusiastic help of strangers as one certainty in an uncertain world.
Peter Ginna, friend to both generations, provided the impetus that set the work going. Each of us relied to such a degree on the talents available in our own homes that this should be considered the work of an extended family.
Rick Kot and his associates at Viking saw the manuscript through to its final form with enthusiasm, professionalism, and dispatch. They, like the others, helped give the book its virtues; its faults are ours alone
1
Thinking
The present is a fleeting moment, the past is no more; and our prospect of futurity is dark and doubtful. This day may
possibly
be my last: but the laws of probability, so true in general, so fallacious in particular, still allow about fifteen years.
—Gibbon,
Memoirs
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
W
e search for certainty and call what we find destiny. Everything is possible, yet only one thing happens—we live and die between these two poles, under the rule of probability. We prefer, though, to call it Chance: an old familiar embodied in gods and demons, harnessed in charms and rituals. We remind one another of fortune's fickleness, each secretly believing himself exempt.
I
am master of my fate;
you
are dicing with danger;
he
is living in a fool's paradise.
Until the 1660s, when John Graunt, a bankrupt London draper, proposed gauging the vitality of his city by its Bills of Mortality, there were only two ways of understanding the world: inductively, by example; or deductively, by axiom. Truths were derived either from experience—and thus hostages to any counterexample lying in ambush—or were beautiful abstractions: pure, consistent, crystalline, but with no certain relevance to the world of mortals. These two modes of reasoning restricted not just the answers we had about life, but the questions we could ask. Beyond, all else was chance, fortune, fate—the riddle of individual existence.
Graunt was the first to unearth truths from heaps of data. His invention, eventually known as statistics, avoided alike the basic question of Being (“all things are possible”) and the uniqueness of individual existence (“only one thing happens”). It got around the problem of uncertainty by asking: “Well, exactly how right do you need to be just now?”
In that same inventive decade, Blaise Pascal was working both on dice-throwing puzzles and on his own, far more compelling, problem: “What shall I do to be saved?” Again, neither induction nor deduction could provide the answers: God and the dice alike refuse to be bound by prior behavior. And yet, and yet . . . in the millennia since Creation, the world has
tended
to be a certain way, just as, over a thousand throws of a die, six
tends
to come up a certain proportion of times. Pascal was the first to see that there could be laws of probability, laws neither fit for Mosaic tablets nor necessarily true for any one time and place, but for life en masse; not for me today, but for mankind through all of time.
The combination of the tool of statistics and the theory of probability is the underpinning of almost all modern sciences, from meteorology to quantum mechanics. It provides justification for almost all purposeful group activity, from politics to economics to medicine to commerce to sports. Once we leave pure mathematics, philosophy, or theology behind, it is the unread footnote to every concrete statement.
And yet it goes against all human instinct. Our natural urge in seeking knowledge is either for deductive logical truth (“Happiness is the highest good”) or for inductive truths based on experience (“Never play cards with a man called Doc”). We want questions to fall into one of these categories, which is one of many reasons most of us find probability alien and statisticians unappealing. They don't tell us what we want to know: the absolute truth. Their science is right everywhere but wrong in any one place: like journalism, it is true except in any case of which we have personal knowledge. And, while we may be willing to take a look at the numbers, we rebel at the idea of
being
one—a “mere statistic.”
But there are people in the world who can dance with data, people for whom this mass of incomplete uncertainties falls beautifully into place, in patterns as delightful and revealing as a flock of migrating swans. Graunt, Pascal, the Reverend Thomas Bayes, Francis Galton, R. A. Fisher, John von Neumann—all are figures a little to the side of life, perhaps trying to puzzle their way toward a grasp of human affairs that the more sociable could acquire glibly through maxim and proverb. The people who use probability today—market-makers, cardplayers, magicians, artificial-intelligence experts, doctors, war-game designers—have an equally interesting and oblique view of the human affairs they analyze and, to an extent, control.
 
If you have ever taken a long car journey with an inquisitive child, you will know most of the difficulties with formal reasoning. Questions like “How do you know that?” and “What if it's not like that?” pose real problems—problems that have kept philosophy hard at work for over two thousand years. “How do you know?” is particularly tricky: you “know” that protons are composed of quarks, or that the President spoke in Duluth because he's courting the union vote—but is this “knowing” the same as knowing that the angles of a triangle add up to 180 degrees, or that you have a slight itch behind your left ear? Intuition says they are
not
the same—but how do you know?
This was the great question in Plato's time, particularly because the Sophists insisted that it was no question at all: their idea was that
persuasion
was the basis of knowledge, and that therefore rhetoric was the form of proof. The Sophist Gorgias promised to give his students “such absolute readiness for speaking, that they should be able to convince their audience
independently of any knowledge of the subject
.” Conviction was enough, since, he believed, nothing actually existed; or if it did, it could not be known; or if it could, it was inexpressible. This view offered the advantage that we could know everything the same way—protons to presidents—but had the disadvantage that we knew nothing very well.
Plato and his circle hated the Sophists for their tort-lawyer cockiness and their marketing of wisdom, but most of all for their relativism. Platonists never accept that things are so just because someone has had the last word; some things are so because they
have
to be. A well-constructed pleading does not make 3 equal 5. Plato's student Euclid arranged his books of geometry into
definitions
of objects;
axioms
, the basic statements of their relations; and
theorems
, statements that can be proved by showing how they are only logical extensions of axioms. A demonstration from Euclid has a powerful effect on any inquiring mind; it takes a statement, often difficult to believe, and in a few steps turns this into knowledge as certain as “I am.”
So why can't all life be like Euclid? After all, if we could express every field of inquiry as a consistent group of axioms, theorems, and proofs, even a president's speech would have one, incontrovertible meaning. This was Aristotle's great plan. The axioms of existence, he said, were matter and form. All things were the expression of form on matter, so the relationship between any two things could be defined by the forms they shared. Mortality, dogness, being from Corinth, or being the prime mover of the universe—all were aspects of being that could be set in their proper, nested order by logical proof. Thus, in the famous first syllogism of every textbook:
 

Other books

The Sex Lives of Cannibals by J. Maarten Troost
Snow Bound Enemies by Donavan, Seraphina
Guerra y paz by Lev Tolstói
Black Harvest by Ann Pilling
Nan-Core by Mahokaru Numata
Pay the Piper by Joan Williams
Between Hell and Texas by Dusty Richards