Read Clinical Handbook of Mindfulness Online
Authors: Fabrizio Didonna,Jon Kabat-Zinn
Tags: #Science, #Physics, #Crystallography, #Chemistry, #Inorganic
described,
between another object
the left hand could be
approached,
and some attribute or
equally matched
manipulated, or
circumstance pertaining to
were they equally
“bought,” so can
Analogies
it” (OED online)
trained” (p. 276)
thoughts and feelings
Metaphors
Transfer a name or a descriptive word or phrase to
an object or action different from [
. . .
] that to which
it is literally applicable (OED online)
Pervasive in vernacular
discourse; ACT stresses
metaphorical or word
Metaphorical origins go
“Hold your tongue”
origin (e.g., discussion
Conventional
unnoticed (Kittay, 1987)
(p. 51)
of “responsibility”)
Human affect, behavior,
Concepts are applied to a
and cognition are
variety of expressions
nested, historical, and
pertaining to the same
ongoing events (Hayes,
topic (Lackoff & Johnson,
“Love is a physical
Wilson, & Strosahl,
Conceptual
1980)
force” (p. 90)
1999, pp. 18–26)
Emotions, thoughts, and
impulses are the cargo
of trains running on
Similarity is generated and
parallel tracks in one’s
not preexisting (Black,
“The garden was a slum
mind (Hayes & Smith,
Creative
1962)
of bloom.” (p. 17)
2005, p. 66)
The story of the person
in the hole (Hayes
“Extended metaphors” (OED
Plato’s
Allegory of the
et al., 1999,
Allegories
online)
Cave
pp. 101–102)
If you aren’t willing to
Express “a general truth
have it, you got it
drawn from science or
(Hayes et al., 1999,
Maxims
experience” (OED online)
pp. 121)
116
Alethea A. Varra, Claudia Drossel, and Steven C. Hayes
direct instruction or detailed rule giving. A body of research in the 1980s
(e.g.,
Barrett, Deitz, Gaydos, & Quinn, 1987; Catania, Matthews, & Shimoff
,
1982; Hayes, Brownstein, Zettle, Rosenfarb, & Korn
,
1986)
demonstrated that people are less likely to meet the changing demands of situations after
having received explicit instructions. In essence, excessive rule-following
may be repertoire narrowing, decreasing the flexibility necessary to mas-
ter life’s challenges. Conversely, more strategic or less-detailed verbal rules
may preserve flexible coping. The Buddhist allegory of
the finger and the
moon
(Watts, 2003)
provides an example: Meticulous instruction following (i.e., attending to the other person’s pointing finger) may prevent contact
with the actually prevailing conditions (seeing what is there to be seen).
Experiential exercises combined with the figurative speech in ACT are
explicitly designed to minimize the role of instruction and to maximize per-
sonal engagement with subtle and complex social situations. They downplay
the therapist’s expert (and potentially coercive) role, amplify the importance
of individual experience, and create a space where the client may begin to
experience events “freely and without defense”
(Hayes et al., 1999,
p. 77).
Flexible approach, rather than rigid avoidance, characterizes the engagement
in life that ACT aims to promote. In line with this understanding, regardless
of ACT’s evidence base and the demonstrated usefulness of the approach,
therapists have to assess whether the use of figurative speech has the desired
impact on the client.
Theories of Figurative Speech
Modern theorists characterize figurative speech as the “constitutive form” of
language and its “omnipresent principle”
(Richards, 1936,
p. 93). While similes and analogies explicitly extend comparative relations and proportions to
other subject matters and were rather uninteresting to linguists, metaphors
have always received more scholarly attention because they seemed to arise
out of a random, creative process that involved an intentional, “degener-
ative, incidental, or non-conforming”
(Ritchie, 2006,
p. 3) misuse of language. After Lakoff and his colleagues pointed to the ubiquity of conceptual
metaphors in language process
(Lakoff & Johnson, 1980, 1999),
linguistic scholars began to distinguish “conventional metaphors”—firmly engrained
in vernacular use, sharing nonverbal experience or a conceptual basis—from
the “creative metaphors” of extraordinary rhetorical construction in speech,
poetry, and literature
(Knowles & Moon, 2006; Rozik, 2007).
RFT
(Hayes et al., 2001)
reconciles these seemingly divergent views (Stewart & Barnes-Holmes,
2001).
RFT shows (1) how correlations between different types of nonverbal or verbal experiences may influence descriptions and
(2) how novel references to nonexisting events may emerge out of purely
verbally constructed relationships. To illustrate, a child commenting that car-
bonated water tastes like “my foot’s asleep” would be an example of the
first type of metaphorical extension
(Skinner, 1957,
p. 92), Shakespeare’s
“O, beware, my lord, of jealousy. It is the green-eyed monster which doth
mock the meat it feeds on” (3.3, 189–192) is an example of the second.
RFT integrates nonverbal events with verbal ones and provides an account
of how never-before-experienced events (e.g., a green-eyed monster) come
Chapter 7 The Use of Metaphor to Establish Acceptance and Mindfulness
117
to exert cognitive meaning as well as emotional effects. Unlike the current
compartmentalized and discontinuous theories of figurative speech, RFT ren-
ders a consistent and comprehensive account of language and cognition that
systematically spans all types of literal and figurative speech, from descrip-
tions over similes to creative metaphors.
The Application of Metaphor
ACT is a theory-driven and contextually based therapy in which the appropri-
ate intervention differs greatly, given the individual client and the presenting
problem. In discussing common ACT metaphors, we encourage therapists to
identify the purpose of the metaphor and adapt the story or technique to
their individual client’s experience. This is congruent with research that sug-
gests that clinical effectiveness of metaphors is increased when metaphors
are produced in collaboration with client, are frequently repeated, and are
apt to the situation
(Martin, Cummings, & Hallberg, 1992).
Thus, while each of the following metaphors is commonly used by ACT therapists, therapists
are encouraged to create their own, similar metaphors in conjunction with
their clients.
Undermine or Avoid Reason Giving
The ACT approach to understanding human suffering postulates that lan-
guage is the basis for a great deal of emotional pain and inflexible behav-
ior. One of the common impediments to behavioral change is reason giving.
Individuals find it difficult to do something new because they have a well-
developed story about why they are doing something old. A classic example
is discussing why a person continues to use a particular coping strategy that
is clearly not working. One approach would be to identify the strategy and
identify reasons the person should do something else. From the ACT perspec-
tive, this simply strengthens reason giving as an appropriate coping strategy
and leaves clients further entrenched in their original suffering. Consider the
following metaphor:
The Person in the Hole Metaphor
The situation you are in seems a bit like this. Imagine that you’re placed in a
field, wearing a blindfold, and you’re given a little bag of tools. You’re told that
your job is to run around this field, blindfolded. That is how you are supposed
to live life. And so you do what you are told. Now unbeknownst to you, in this
field there are a number of widely spaced, fairly deep holes. You don’t know
that at first—you’re naive. So you start running around and sooner or later you
fall into this large hole. You feel around and sure enough you can’t climb out
and there are no escape routes you can find. Probably what you would do in
such a predicament is take the bag of tools you were given and see what is
in there: Maybe there is something you can use to get out of the hole. Now
suppose that there is a tool in that bag but what you’ve been given is a shovel.
It’s seemingly all you’ve got. So you dutifully start digging, but pretty soon you
notice that you’re not out of the hole. So you try digging faster, and faster. But
you’re still in the hole. So you try big shovelfuls, or little ones, or throwing the
dirt far away or not. But still you are in the hole. All this effort and all this work
118
Alethea A. Varra, Claudia Drossel, and Steven C. Hayes
and oddly enough the hole has just gotten bigger and bigger and bigger. Hasn’t
it? So you come in to see me thinking “maybe he has a really huge shovel—
a gold-plated steam shovel.” Well, I don’t. And even if I did I wouldn’t use it
because digging is not a way out of the hole—digging is what makes holes. So
maybe the whole agenda is hopeless—you can’t dig your way out, that just digs
you in.
(Hayes et al., 1999,
pp. 101–102)
One function of this metaphor is to undermine reason giving. The
metaphor acknowledges that the person may have reasons and that those
reasons make quite logical sense. However, the metaphor puts at the fore-
front the question of whether or not what the person is doing is working.
Reasons are undermined in that they are less important than the measure
of workability. The therapist need not debate the individual’s reasons nor
convince their clients of the supremacy of other reasons.
Undermine or Avoid Pliance
As discussed above, while rule-following may decrease the flexibility neces-
sary to master life’s challenges, sufficiently vague rules may preserve flexi-
ble coping. Metaphors are particularly useful in undermining pliance in part
for this reason. There is often no correct response or answer following a
metaphor. In ACT, this is sometimes addressed directly in discussion of the
therapeutic relationship. This is an example:
Two Mountains Metaphor
It’s like you’re in the process of climbing up a big mountain that has lots of
dangerous places on it. My job is to watch out for you and shout out directions
if I can see places you might slip or hurt yourself. The question is how do I best
do that? If I am at the top of your mountain, then I can’t really see you very well.
If I am leading you up the mountain, then I have the same view as you and that
isn’t much help either. I see it like I am actually on my own mountain, just the
one across the valley. From there I have a good view of your path. I don’t have
to know anything about exactly what it feels like to climb your mountain to see
where you are about to step. You are the expert on your mountain and what it
feels like to be there. I have the advantage of being able to see from a different
perspective. Together we might be able to figure out a way to climb.
At other times, the metaphor is used to give a specific message, but the
expected change in behavior is not articulated by the therapist
The Rubber Hammer Metaphor
It would be as if you were to go to the doctor and say that you have a terrible
headache, and the doctor looks at you and you’re hitting yourself in the head
with a rubber hammer. You may not know that you’re hitting yourself, or you
might have a very good reason for doing so. However, the first thing the doctor
is likely to tell you is “you are hitting yourself over the head with a hammer,
and your head is likely to continue to hurt until that stops.”
In this situation, the patient must decide what the hammer is and what
it means to stop hitting oneself over the head with it. Pliance is reduced
Chapter 7 The Use of Metaphor to Establish Acceptance and Mindfulness
119
because the therapist does not explicitly define the rule. The resulting effect
more closely resembles contingency shaping than a direct rule because a
very wide variety of actions could be relevant to the metaphor.
Weaken Literal Functions of Language
Because of the emphasis on language in ACT, there are many metaphors that
specifically target the literal functions of language. These metaphors are used
to highlight the pitfalls of taking our thoughts and the associated language
literally, and seek to establish contexts in which that is less likely. This is an
example.
Two Computers Metaphor
Imagine two computers, sitting side by side, each with an operator in front of
them. These are identical machines, and they have the same programs and the
same data in them. Now, the way computers work is that if you give them a par-
ticular input, they give a particular output. So suppose we push a key on these