Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
destroy traditional social boundaries, expanding across territories
and enveloping always new populations within its processes. Capital
functions, according to the terminology of Deleuze and Guattari,
through a generalized decoding offluxes, a massive deterritorializa-
tion, and then through conjunctions ofthese deterritorialized and
decoded fluxes.1 We can understand the functioning of capital as
deterritorializing and immanent in three primary aspects that Marx
himselfanalyzed. First, in the processes ofprimitive accumulation,
capital separates populations from specifically coded territories and
sets them in motion. It clears the Estates and creates a ‘‘free’’ proletar-
iat. Traditional cultures and social organizations are destroyed in
capital’s tireless march through the world to create the networks
and pathways ofa single cultural and economic system ofproduction
and circulation. Second, capital brings all forms of value together
on one common plane and links them all through money, their
general equivalent. Capital tends to reduce all previously established
forms ofstatus, title, and privilege to the level ofthe cash nexus,
that is, to quantitative and commensurable economic terms. Third,
the laws by which capital functions are not separate and fixed laws
that stand above and direct capital’s operations from on high, but
historically variable laws that are immanent to the very functioning
ofcapital: the laws ofthe rate ofprofit, the rate ofexploitation,
the realization ofsurplus value, and so forth.
Capital therefore demands not a transcendent power but a
mechanism ofcontrol that resides on the plane ofimmanence.
Through the social development ofcapital, the mechanisms of
modern sovereignty—the processes ofcoding, overcoding, and
recoding that imposed a transcendent order over a bounded and
segmented social terrain—are progressively replaced by an
axiomatic:
that is, a set ofequations and relationships that determines and
combines variables and coefficients immediately and equally across
C A P I T A L I S T S O V E R E I G N T Y
327
various terrains without reference to prior and fixed definitions or
terms.2 The primary characteristic ofsuch an axiomatic is that
relations are prior to their terms. In other words, within an axiomatic
system, postulates ‘‘are not propositions that can be true or false,
since they contain relatively indeterminate
variables.
Only when we give these variables particular values, or in other words, when we
substitute constants for them, do the postulates become propositions,
true or false, according to the constants chosen.’’3 Capital operates
through just such an axiomatic ofpropositional f
unctions. The
general equivalence ofmoney brings all elements together in quanti-
fiable, commensurable relations, and then the immanent laws or
equations ofcapital determine their deployment and relation accord-
ing to the particular constants that are substituted for the variables
ofthe equations. Just as an axiomatic destabilizes any terms and
definitions prior to the relations oflogical deduction, so too capital
sweeps clear the fixed barriers ofprecapitalist society—and even
the boundaries ofthe nation-state tend to fade into the background
as capital realizes itselfin the world market. Capital tends toward
a smooth space defined by uncoded flows, flexibility, continual
modulation, and tendential equalization.4
The transcendence ofmodern sovereignty thus conflicts with
the immanence ofcapital. Historically, capital has relied on sover-
eignty and the support ofits structures ofright and force, but those
same structures continually contradict in principle and obstruct in
practice the operation ofcapital, finally obstructing its development.
The entire history ofmodernity that we have traced thus far might
be seen as the evolution ofthe attempts to negotiate and mediate
this contradiction. The historical process ofmediation has been not
an equal give and take, but rather a one-sided movement from
sovereignty’s transcendent position toward capital’s plane ofimma-
nence. Foucault traces this movement in his analysis ofthe passage
in European rule between the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
from ‘‘sovereignty’’ (an absolute form of sovereignty centralized in
the will and person ofthe Prince) and ‘‘governmentality’’ (a form
328
P A S S A G E S O F P R O D U C T I O N
ofsovereignty expressed through a decentralized economy ofrule
and management ofgoods and populations).5 This passage between
forms of sovereignty coincides importantly with the early develop-
ment and expansion ofcapital. Each ofthe modern paradigms of
sovereignty indeed supports capital’s operation for a specific histori-
cal period, but at the same time they pose obstacles to capital’s
development that eventually have to be overcome. This evolving
relationship is perhaps the central problematic to be confronted by
any theory ofthe capitalist state.
Civil society served for one historical period as mediator be-
tween the immanent forces of capital and the transcendent power
ofmodern sovereignty. Hegel adopted the term ‘‘civil society’’ from
his reading ofBritish economists, and he understood it as a mediation
between the self-interested endeavors of a plurality of economic
individuals and the unified interest ofthe state. Civil society mediates
between the (immanent) Many and the (transcendent) One. The
institutions that constitute civil society functioned as passageways
that channel flows ofsocial and economic forces, raising them up
toward a coherent unity and, flowing back, like an irrigation net-
work, distribute the command ofthe unity throughout the imma-
nent social field. These non-state institutions, in other words, orga-
nized capitalist society under the order ofthe state and in turn
spread state rule throughout society. In the terms ofour conceptual
framework, we might say that civil society was the terrain of the
becoming-immanent ofmodern state sovereignty (down to capitalist
society) and at the same time inversely the becoming-transcendent
ofcapitalist society (up to the state).
In our times, however, civil society no longer serves as the
adequate point ofmediation between capital and sovereignty. The
structures and institutions that constitute it are today progressively
withering away. We have argued elsewhere that this withering can
be grasped clearly in terms ofthe decline ofthe dialectic between
the capitalist state and labor, that is, in the decline of the effectiveness and role oflabor unions, the decline ofcollective bargaining with
labor, and the decline ofthe representation oflabor in the constitu-
C A P I T A L I S T S O V E R E I G N T Y
329
tion.6 The withering ofcivil society might also be recognized as
concomitant with the passage from disciplinary society to the society
ofcontrol (see Section 2.6). Today the social institutions that consti-
tute disciplinary society (the school, the family, the hospital, the
factory), which are in large part the same as or closely related to
those understood as civil society, are everywhere in crisis. As the
walls ofthese institutions break down, the logics ofsubjectification
that previously operated within their limited spaces now spread
out, generalized across the social field. The breakdown ofthe institu-
tions, the withering ofcivil society, and the decline ofdisciplinary
society all involve a smoothing ofthe striation ofmodern social
space. Here arise the networks ofthe society ofcontrol.7
With respect to disciplinary society and civil society, the society
ofcontrol marks a step toward the plane ofimmanence. The disci-
plinary institutions, the boundaries of the effectivity of their logics,
and their striation ofsocial space all constitute instances ofverticality
or transcendence over the social plane. We should be careful, how-
ever, to locate where exactly this transcendence ofdisciplinary
society resides. Foucault was insistent on the fact, and this was the
brilliant core ofhis analysis, that the exercise ofdiscipline is abso-
lutely immanent to the subjectivities under its command. In other
words, discipline is not an external voice that dictates our practices
from on high, overarching us, as Hobbes would say, but rather
something like an inner compulsion indistinguishable from our
will, immanent to and inseparable from our subjectivity itself. The
institutions that are the condition ofpossibility and that define
spatially the zones of effectivity of the exercise of discipline, how-
ever, do maintain a certain separation from the social forces pro-
duced and organized. They are in effect an instance of sovereignty,
or rather a point ofmediation with sovereignty. The walls ofthe
prison both enable and limit the exercise ofcarceral logics. They
differentiate social space.
Foucault negotiates with enormous subtlety this distance be-
tween the transcendent walls ofthe institutions and the immanent
exercise ofdiscipline through his theories ofthe
dispositif
and the 330
P A S S A G E S O F P R O D U C T I O N
diagram, which articulate a series ofstages ofabstraction.8 In some-
what simplified terms, we can say that the
dispositif
(which is translated as either mechanism, apparatus, or deployment) is the general
strategy that stands behind the immanent and actual exercise of
discipline. Carceral logic, for example, is the unified dispositif that
oversees or subtends—and is thus abstracted and distinct from—the
multiplicity ofprison practices. At a second level ofabstraction, the
diagram
enables the deployments ofthe disciplinary dispositif. For example, the carceral architecture ofthe panopticon, which makes
inmates constantly visible to a central point ofpower, is the diagram
or virtual design that is actualized in the various disciplinary dispos-
itifs. Finally, the institutions themselves instantiate the diagram in
particular and concrete social forms as well. The prison (its walls,
administrators, guards, laws, and so forth) does not rule its inmates
the way a sovereign commands its subjects. It creates a space in
which inmates, through the strategies ofcarceral dispositif
s and
through actual practices,
discipline themselves.
It would be more
precise to say, then, that the disciplinary institution is not itself
sovereign, but its abstraction from or transcendence above the social
field ofthe production ofsubjectivity constitutes the key element
in the exercise ofsovereignty in disciplinary society. Sovereignty
has become virtual (but it is for that no less real), and it is actualized
always and everywhere through the exercise ofdiscipline.
Today the collapse ofthe walls that delimited the institutions
and the smoothing ofsocial striation are symptoms ofthe flattening
ofthese vertical instances toward the horizontality ofthe circuits
ofcontrol. The passage to the society ofcontrol does not in any
way mean the end ofdiscipline. In fact, the immanent exercise of
discipline—that is, the self-disciplining of subjects, the incessant
whisperings ofdisciplinary logics within subjectivities them-
selves—is extended even more generally in the society ofcontrol.
What has changed is that, along with the collapse ofthe institutions,
the disciplinary dispositifs have become less limited and bounded
spatially in the social field. Carceral discipline, school discipline,
factory discipline, and so forth interweave in a hybrid production
C A P I T A L I S T S O V E R E I G N T Y
331
of subjectivity. In effect, in the passage to the society of control,
the elements oftranscendence ofdisciplinary society decline while
the immanent aspects are accentuated and generalized.
The immanent production ofsubjectivity in the society of
control corresponds to the axiomatic logic ofcapital, and their
resemblance indicates a new and more complete compatibility be-
tween sovereignty and capital. The production ofsubjectivity in
civil society and disciplinary society did in a certain period further
the rule and facilitate the expansion of capital. The modern social
institutions produced social identities that were much more mobile
and flexible than the previous subjective figures. The subjectivities
produced in the modern institutions were like the standardized
machine parts produced in the mass factory: the inmate, the mother,
the worker, the student, and so forth. Each part played a specific
role in the assembled machine, but it was standardized, produced
en masse, and thus replaceable with any part ofits type. At a certain
point, however, the fixity ofthese standardized parts, ofthe identities
produced by the institutions, came to pose an obstacle to the further
progression toward mobility and flexibility. The passage toward the
society ofcontrol involves a production ofsubjectivity that is not