Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
to the concept of modernity, but it was effectively dominated and
held in check. The cultural and religious revolutions were forced
toward rigid and sometimes ferocious structures of containment.
In the seventeenth century, Europe became feudal again. The
counterreformist Catholic Church was the first and most effective
example ofthis reaction, because that church itselfearlier had been
rocked by an earthquake ofreform and revolutionary desire. The
Protestant churches and political orders were not far behind in
producing the order ofthe counterrevolution. Throughout Europe
the fires ofsuperstition were lit. And yet the movements ofrenewal
continued their work ofliberation at the base. Whereever spaces
were closed, movements turned to nomadism and exodus, carrying
with them the desire and hope ofan irrepressible experience.13
The internal conflict ofEuropean modernity was also reflected
simultaneously on a global scale as an external conflict. The develop-
ment ofRenaissance thought coincided both with the European
discovery ofthe Americas and with the beginnings ofEuropean
dominance over the rest ofthe world. Europe had discovered its
outside. ‘‘Ifthe period ofthe Renaissance marks a qualitative break
in the history ofhumanity,’’ writes Samir Amin, ‘‘it is precisely
because, from that time on, Europeans become conscious of the
idea that the conquest ofthe world by their civilization is henceforth
a possible objective . . . From this moment on, and not before,
Eurocentrism crystallizes.’’14 On the one hand, Renaissance human-
ism initiated a revolutionary notion ofhuman equality, ofsingularity
and community, cooperation and multitude, that resonated with
forces and desires extending horizontally across the globe, redoubled
by the discovery ofother populations and territories. On the other
hand, however, the same counterrevolutionary power that sought
to control the constituent and subversive forces within Europe also
began to realize the possibility and necessity ofsubordinating other
T W O E U R O P E S , T W O M O D E R N I T I E S
77
populations to European domination. Eurocentrism was born as a
reaction to the potentiality ofa newfound human equality; it was
the counterrevolution on a global scale. Here too the second mode
ofmodernity gained the upper hand, but again not in a definitive
way. European modernity is from its beginnings a war on two
fronts. European mastery is always in crisis—and this is the very
same crisis that defines European modernity.
In the seventeenth century the concept ofmodernity as crisis
was definitively consolidated. The century began with the burning
ofGiordano Bruno at the stake, and it went on to see monstrous
civil wars break out in France and England, and above all it witnessed
the horrible spectacle ofthirty years ofGerman civil war. At the
same time, the European conquest ofthe Americas and the slaughter
and enslavement ofits native populations proceeded with ever-
increasing intensity. In the second halfofthe century, monarchic
absolutism seemed definitively to block the course offreedom in
the countries ofcontinental Europe. Absolutism sought to fix the
concept ofmodernity and strip it ofthe crisis that defines it through
the deployment ofa new armory oftranscendentals. At the same
time, outside ofEurope conquest slowly gave way to colonialism,
and the precarious search for gold, riches, and plunder was progres-
sively displaced by trade exclusives, stable forms of production, and
the African slave trade. The seventeenth century, however—and
this is what makes it so ambiguous—was a fragile, baroque century.
From the abysses ofthe social world always arose the memory of
what it tried to bury.
We can find testimony to this fact with one single but enor-
mous reference: Spinoza’s philosophy of immanence, which domi-
nated the latter halfofthe century ofEuropean thought. It is a
philosophy that renewed the splendors ofrevolutionary humanism,
putting humanity and nature in the position ofGod, transforming
the world into a territory ofpractice, and affirming the democracy
ofthe multitude as the absolute form ofpolitics. Spinoza considered
the idea ofdeath—that death that states and powers carried like a
weapon against the desire and hope ofliberation—merely a hostage
78
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
used to blackmail the freedom of thought, and thus banned it from
his philosophy: ‘ A free man thinks about nothing less than of death,
and his knowledge is a meditation on life, not on death.’’15 That love
that the humanists considered the supreme form of the expression of
intelligence was posed by Spinoza as the only possible foundation
ofthe liberation ofsingularities and as the ethical cement ofcollec-
tive life. ‘‘There is nothing in nature which is contrary to this
intellectual Love, or which can take it away.’’16 In this crescendo
ofthought, Spinoza testified to the uninterrupted continuity ofthe
revolutionary program ofhumanism in the course ofthe seven-
teenth century.
The Transcendental Apparatus
The counterrevolutionary project to resolve the crisis ofmodernity
unfolded in the centuries of the Enlightenment.17 The primary task
ofthis Enlightenment was to dominate the idea ofimmanence
without reproducing the absolute dualism ofmedieval culture by
constructing a transcendental apparatus capable ofdisciplining a
multitude of formally free subjects. The ontological dualism of the
culture ofthe ancien re´gime had to be replaced by a functional
dualism, and the crisis ofmodernity had to be resolved by means
ofadequate mechanisms ofmediation. It was paramount to avoid the
multitude’s being understood, à la Spinoza, in a direct, immediate
relation with divinity and nature, as the ethical producer oflife and
the world. On the contrary, in every case mediation had to be
imposed on the complexity ofhuman relations. Philosophers dis-
puted where this mediation was situated and what metaphysical
level it occupied, but it was fundamental that in some way it be
defined as an ineluctable condition ofall human action, art, and
association. Hence the triad
vis-cupiditas-amor
(strength-desire-love) which constituted the productive matrix ofthe revolutionary
thought ofhumanism was opposed by a triad ofspecific mediations.
Nature and experience are unrecognizable except through
the filter
of phenomena;
human knowledge cannot be achieved except through
the reflection of the intellect;
and the ethical world is incommunicable T W O E U R O P E S , T W O M O D E R N I T I E S
79
except through the
schematism of reason.
What is at play is a form ofmediation, or really a reflexive folding back and a sort ofweak
transcendence, which relativizes experience and abolishes every
instance ofthe immediate and absolute in human life and history.
Why, however, is this relativity necessary? Why cannot knowledge
and will be allowed to claim themselves to be absolute? Because
every movement ofself-constitution ofthe multitude must yield
to a preconstituted order, and because claiming that humans could
immediately establish their freedom in being would be a subversive
delirium. This is the essential core ofthe ideological passage in which
the hegemonic concept ofEuropean modernity was constructed.
The first strategic masterpiece in this construction was accom-
plished by Rene´ Descartes. Although Descartes pretended to pursue
a new humanistic project ofknowledge, he really reestablished
transcendent order. When he posed reason as the exclusive terrain
of mediation between God and the world, he effectively reaffirmed
dualism as the defining feature of experience and thought. We
should be careful here. Mediation in Descartes is never well defined,
or really, ifwe stay close to the text, we find that mediation resides
mysteriously only in the will ofGod. Descartes’s cunning stratagem
consists primarily in this: When he addresses the centrality ofthought
in the transcendental function of mediation, he defines a sort of
residual ofdivine transcendence. Descartes claims that the logics of
mediation reside in thought and that God is very far from the scene,
but a new man such as Blaise Pascal is perfectly right to object that
this is just an example ofDescartes’s trickery.18 In fact, Descartes’s
God is very close: God is the guarantee that transcendental rule is
inscribed in consciousness and thought as necessary, universal, and
thus preconstituted:
Please do not hesitate to assert and proclaim everywhere that
it is God who has laid down these laws in nature just as a
king lays down laws in his kingdom. There is no single one
that we cannot understand ifour mind turns to consider it.
They are all inborn in our minds just as a king would imprint
80
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
his laws on the hearts ofall his subjects ifhe had enough
power to do so. The greatness ofGod, on the other hand, is
something which we cannot comprehend even though we
know it. But the very fact that we judge it incomprehensible
makes us esteem it the more greatly; just as a king has more
majesty when he is less familiarly known by his subjects, pro-
vided ofcourse that they do not get the idea that they have
no king—they must know him enough to be in no doubt
about that.19
The realm ofpotentiality, which had been opened by the humanist
principle ofsubjectivity, is limited a priori by the imposition of
transcendent rule and order. Descartes surreptitiously reproposes
theology on the terrain that humanism had cleared, and its apparatus
is resolutely transcendental.
With Descartes we are at the beginning ofthe history ofthe
Enlightenment, or rather bourgeois ideology.20 The transcendental
apparatus he proposes is the distinctive trademark ofEuropean
Enlightenment thought. In both the empiricist and the idealist
currents, transcendentalism was the exclusive horizon ofideology,
and in the successive centuries nearly all the major currents of
philosophy would be drawn into this project. The symbiosis be-
tween intellectual labor and institutional, political, and scientific
rhetorics became absolute on this terrain, and every conceptual
formation came to be marked by it: the formalization of politics,
the instrumentalization ofscience and technique f
or profit, the
pacification ofsocial antagonisms. Certainly, in each ofthese fields
we find historically specific developments, but everything was al-
ways tied up with the line ofa grand narrative that European
modernity told about itself, a tale told in a transcendental dialect.21
In many respects the work ofImmanuel Kant stands at the
center ofthis development. Kant’s thought is enormously rich and
leads in numerous directions, but we are interested here primarily
in the line that crowns the transcendental principle as the apex of
European modernity. Kant manages to pose the subject at the center
T W O E U R O P E S , T W O M O D E R N I T I E S
81
ofthe metaphysical horizon but at the same time control it by
means ofthe three operations we cited earlier: the emptying of
experience in phenomena, the reduction ofknowledge to intellec-
tual mediation, and the neutralization ofethical action in the sche-
matism ofreason. The mediation that Descartes invoked in his
reaffirmation of dualism is hypostatized by Kant, not in the divinity
but nonetheless in a pseudo-ontological critique—in an ordering
function ofconsciousness and an indistinct appetite ofthe will.
Humanity is the center ofthe universe, but this is not the humanity
that through art and action made itself
homohomo.
It is a humanity lost in experience, deluded in the pursuit ofthe ethical ideal. Kant
throws us back into the crisis ofmodernity with full awareness
when he poses the discovery ofthe subject itselfas crisis, but this
crisis is made into an apology ofthe transcendental as the unique
and exclusive horizon ofknowledge and action. The world becomes
an architecture ofideal forms, the only reality conceded to us.
Romanticism was never expressed so strongly as it is in Kant.
This is the leitmotifofKantian philosophy: the necessity ofthe
transcendental, the impossibility ofevery form ofimmediacy, the
exorcism ofevery vital figure in the apprehension and action of
being. From this perspective one should perhaps consider Arthur
Schopenhauer the most lucid reader ofKantianism and its Romantic
gesture. The fact that it is difficult if not impossible to reunite the
appearance ofthe thing with the thing itselfis precisely the curse
ofthis world ofpain and need. And this is therefore not a world
constructed in a way so that noble and high forces, forces that tend
to truth and light, can prosper.22 In other words, Schopenhauer
recognizes Kantianism as the definitive liquidation ofthe human-