Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
Thomasius to Puffendorf, the transcendental figures of sovereignty
were brought down to earth and grounded in the reality ofthe
institutional and administrative processes. Sovereignty was distrib-
uted by setting in motion a system ofmultiple contracts designed
to intervene on every node ofthe administrative structure ofpower.
This process was not oriented toward the apex ofthe state and the
mere title ofsovereignty; rather, the problem oflegitimation began
to be addressed in terms ofan
administrative machine
that functioned through the articulations ofthe exercise ofpower. The circle of
sovereignty and obedience closed in on itself, duplicating itself,
multiplying, and extending across social reality. Sovereignty came
to be studied less from the perspective of the antagonists involved
in the crisis ofmodernity and more as an administrative process
that articulates these antagonisms and aims toward a unity in the
dialectic ofpower, abstacting and reifying it through the historical
dynamics. An important segment ofthe natural right school thus
developed the idea ofdistributing and articulating the transcendent
sovereignty through the real forms of administration.11
The synthesis that was implicit in the natural right school,
however, became explicit in the context ofhistoricism. Certainly,
it would be incorrect to attribute to the historicism ofthe Enlighten-
ment the thesis that was really only developed later by the reactionary
schools in the period after the French Revolution—the thesis, that
100
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
is, that unites the theory ofsovereignty with the theory ofthe
nation and grounds both ofthem in a common historical humus.
And yet there are already in this early period the seeds ofthat later
development. Whereas an important segment ofthe natural right
school developed the idea ofarticulating transcendent sovereignty
through the real forms of administration, the historicist thinkers of
the Enlightenment attempted to conceive
the subjectivity of the historical process
and thereby find an effective ground for the title and exercise ofsovereignty.12 In the work ofGiambattista Vico, for
example, that terrific meteor that shot across the age ofEnlighten-
ment, the determinations ofthe juridical conception ofsovereignty
were all grounded in the power ofhistorical development. The
transcendent figures ofsovereignty were translated into indexes of
a providential process, which was at once both human and divine.
This construction ofsovereignty (or really reification ofsovereignty)
in history was very powerful. On this historical terrain, which forces
every ideological construct to confront reality, the genetic crisis of
modernity was never closed—and there was no need for it to close,
because the crisis itselfproduced new figures that incessantly spurred
on historical and political development, all still under the rule of
the transcendent sovereign. What an ingenious inversion ofthe
problematic! And yet, at the same time, what a complete mystifica-
tion ofsovereignty! The elements ofthe crisis, a continuous and
unresolved crisis, were now considered active elements ofprogress.
In effect, we can already recognize in Vico the embryo of Hegel’s
apologia of ‘‘effectiveness,’’ making the present world arrangement
the telos ofhistory.13
What remained hints and suggestions in Vico, however,
emerged as an open and radical declaration in the late German
Enlightenment. In the Hannover school first, and then in the work
ofJ. G. Herder, the modern theory ofsovereignty was directed
exclusively toward the analysis ofwhat was conceived as a social
and cultural continuity: the real historical continuity ofthe territory,
the population, and the nation. Vico’s argument that ideal history
is located in the history ofall nations became more radical in Herder
S O V E R E I G N T Y O F T H E N A T I O N - S T A T E
101
so that every human perfection is, in a certain respect, national.14
Identity is thus conceived not as the resolution ofsocial and historical
differences but as the product of a primordial unity. The nation is
a complete figure ofsovereignty
prior
to historical development; or better, there is no historical development that is not already prefigured in the origin. In other words, the nation sustains the concept
ofsovereignty by claiming to precede it.15 It is the material engine
that courses throughout history, the ‘‘genius’’ that works history.
The nation becomes finally the condition ofpossibility ofall human
action and social life itself.
TheNation’s People
Between the end ofthe eighteenth and the beginning ofthe nine-
teenth centuries, the concept ofnational sovereignty finally emerged
in European thought in its completed form. At the base of this
definitive figure ofthe concept were a trauma, the French Revolu-
tion, and the resolution ofthat trauma, the reactionary appropriation
and celebration ofthe concept ofnation. The fundamental elements
ofthis swift reconfiguration ofthe concept ofnation that made it
a real political weapon can be seen in summary form in the work
ofEmmanuel-Joseph Sieyès. In his wonderful and libelous tract
What Is the Third Estate?
he linked the concept ofnation to that
ofthe Third Estate, that is, the bourgeoisie. Sieyès tried to lead the
concept ofsovereignty back to its humanist origins and rediscover
its revolutionary possibilities. More important for our purposes,
Sieyès’s intense engagement with revolutionary activity allowed
him to interpret the concept ofnation as a
constructive political concept,
a constitutional mechanism. It gradually becomes clear, however,
particularly in Sieyès’s later work, the work ofhis followers, and
above all that ofhis detractors, that although the nation was formed
through politics, it was ultimately a
spiritual construction,
and the concept ofnation was thus stripped away f
rom the revolution,
consigned to all the Thermidors. The nation became explicitly the
concept that summarized the bourgeois hegemonic solution to the
problem ofsovereignty.16
102
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
At those points when the concept ofnation has been presented
as popular and revolutionary, as indeed it was during the French
Revolution, one might assume that the nation has broken away
from the modern concept ofsovereignty and its apparatus ofsubju-
gation and domination, and is dedicated instead to a democratic
notion ofcommunity. The link between the concept ofnation and
the concept ofpeople was indeed a powerful innovation, and it
did constitute the center ofthe Jacobin sensibility as well as that
ofother revolutionary groups. What appears as revolutionary and
liberatory in this notion ofnational, popular sovereignty, however,
is really nothing more than another turn ofthe screw, a further
extension ofthe subjugation and domination that the modern con-
cept ofsovereignty has carried with it from the beginning. The
precarious power ofsovereignty as a solution to the crisis ofmoder-
nity was first referred for support to the nation, and then when the
nation too was revealed as a precarious solution, it was further
referred to the people. In other words, just as the concept of nation
completes the notion ofsovereignty by claiming to precede it, so
too the concept ofthe people completes that ofnation through
another feigned logical regression. Each logical step back functions
to solidify the power of sovereignty by mystifying its basis, that is,
by resting on the naturalness ofthe concept. The identity ofthe
nation and even more so the identity ofthe people must appear
natural and originary.
We, by contrast, must de-naturalize these concepts and ask
what is a nation and how is it made, but also, what is a people and
how is it made? Although ‘‘the people’’ is posed as the originary
basis ofthe nation,
the modern conception of the people is in fact a product
of the nation-state,
and survives only within its specific ideological context. Many contemporary analyses ofnations and nationalism
from a wide variety of perspectives go wrong precisely because
they rely unquestioningly on the naturalness ofthe concept and
identity ofthe people. We should note that the concept ofthe
people is very different from that of the multitude.17 Already in the
seventeenth century, Hobbes was very mindful of this difference
S O V E R E I G N T Y O F T H E N A T I O N - S T A T E
103
and its importance for the construction of sovereign order: ‘‘It is a
great hindrance to civil government, especially monarchical, that
men distinguish not enough between a people and a multitude.
The people is somewhat that is one, having one will, and to whom
one action may be attributed; none ofthese can be properly said
ofthe multitude. The people rules in all governments. For even
in monarchies the people commands; for the people wills by the
will ofone man . . . (however it seem a paradox) the king is the
people.’’18 The multitude is a multiplicity, a plane ofsingularities,
an open set ofrelations, which is not homogeneous or identical
with itselfand bears an indistinct, inclusive relation to those outside
ofit. The people, in contrast, tends toward identity and homogene-
ity internally while posing its difference from and excluding what
remains outside ofit. Whereas the multitude is an inconclusive
constituent relation, the people is a constituted synthesis that is
prepared for sovereignty. The people provides a single will and
action that is independent ofand often in conflict with the various
wills and actions ofthe multitude. Every nation must make the
multitude into a people.
Two fundamental kinds of operations contribute to the con-
struction ofthe modern concept ofthe people in relation to that
ofthe nation in Europe in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
The more important ofthese are the mechanisms ofcolonial racism
that construct the identity ofEuropean peoples in a dialectical play
ofoppositions with their native Others. The concepts ofnation,
people, and race are never very far apart.19 The construction ofan
absolute racial difference is the essential ground for the conception
ofa homogeneous national identity. Numerous excellent studies
are appearing today, when the pressures ofimmigration and multi-
culturalism are creating conflicts in Europe, to demonstrate that,
despite the persistent nostalgia ofsome, European societies and
peoples were never really pure and uniform.20 The identity ofthe
people was constructed on an imaginary plane that hid and/or
eliminated differences, and this corresponded on the practical plane
to racial subordination and social purification.
104
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
The second fundamental operation in the construction of the
people, which is facilitated by the first, is the eclipse of internal
differences through the
representation
ofthe whole population by a hegemonic group, race, or class. The representative group is the
active agent that stands behind the effectiveness of the concept of
nation. In the course ofthe French Revolution itself
, between
Thermidor and the Napoleonic period, the concept ofnation re-
vealed its fundamental content and served as an antidote to the
concept and forces of revolution. Even in Sieyès’s early work we
can see clearly how the nation serves to placate the crisis and how
sovereignty will be reappropriated through the representation of
the bourgeoisie. Sieyès claims that a nation can have only
one
general interest: it would be impossible to establish order ifthe nation were
to admit several different interests. Social order necessarily supposes
the
unity
ofends and the concert ofmeans.21 The concept ofnation
in these early years ofthe French Revolution was the first hypothesis
ofthe construction ofpopular hegemony and the first conscious
manifesto ofa social class, but it was also the final declaration ofa
fully accomplished secular transformation, a coronation, a final seal.
Never was the concept ofnation so reactionary as when it presented
itselfas revolutionary.22 Paradoxically, this cannot but be a com-
pleted revolution, an end ofhistory. The passage from revolutionary
activity to the spiritual construction ofthe nation and the people
is inevitable and implicit in the concepts themselves.23
National sovereignty and popular sovereignty were thus prod-
ucts ofa spiritual construction, that is, a construction ofidentity.
When Edmund Burke opposed Sieyès, his position was much less
profoundly different than the torrid polemical climate of the age
would lead us to believe. Even for Burke, in fact, national sover-
eignty is the product ofa spiritual construction ofidentity. This
fact can be recognized even more clearly in the work of those who