Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
humanism is the utopia that anchors this revolutionary principle.
The second Machiavellian principle at work here is that the social
base ofthis democratic sovereignty is always conflictual. Power is
organized through the emergence and the interplay ofcounterpow-
ers. The city is thus a constituent power that is formed through
plural social conflicts articulated in continuous constitutional pro-
cesses. This is how Machiavelli read the organization ofrepublican
ancient Rome, and this is how the Renaissance notion ofthe city
served as the foundation for a realist political theory and practice:
social conflict is the basis ofthe stability ofpower and the logic ofthe
city’s expansion. Machiavelli’s thought inaugurated a Copernican
N E T W O R K P O W E R : U . S . S O V E R E I G N T Y
163
revolution that reconfigured politics as perpetual movement. These
are the primary teachings that the Atlantic doctrine ofdemocracy
derived from the republican Machiavelli.4
This republican Rome was not the only Rome that fascinated
Machiavelli and guided the Atlantic republicans. Their new ‘‘science
ofpolitics’’ was also inspired by imperial Rome, particularly as it
was presented in the writings ofPolybius. In the first place, Polybius’
model ofimperial Rome grounded more solidly the republican
process ofthe mediation ofsocial powers and brought it to a
conclusion in a synthesis ofdiverse forms ofgovernment. Polybius
conceived the perfect form of power as structured by a mixed
constitution that combines monarchic power, aristocratic power,
and democratic power.5 The new political scientists in the United
States organized these three powers as the three branches ofthe
republican constitution. Any disequilibrium among these powers,
and this is the second sign ofPolybius’ influence, is a symptom of
corruption. The Machiavellian Constitution ofthe United States
is a structure poised against corruption—the corruption ofboth
factions and individuals, of groups and the state. The Constitution
was designed to resist any cyclical decline into corruption by activat-
ing the entire multitude and organizing its constituent capacity
in networks oforganized counterpowers, in flows ofdiverse and
equalized functions, and in a process of dynamic and expansive
self-regulation.
These ancient models, however, go only so far in characterizing
the U.S. experience, because in many respects it was truly new and
original. In very different periods, Alexis de Tocqueville and Han-
nah Arendt both grasped the novelty ofthis new ideology and new
form ofpower. Tocqueville was the more cautious ofthe two.
Although he recognized the vitality ofthe new political world in
the United States and saw how the synthesis ofdiverse forms of
government had been forged into a regulated mass democracy, he
also claimed to have seen in America the democratic revolution
reach its natural limits. His judgment about whether American
democracy can avoid the old cycle ofcorruption was thus mixed
164
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
when not outright pessimistic.6 Hannah Arendt, by contrast, unre-
servedly celebrated American democracy as the site ofthe invention
ofmodern politics itself. The central idea ofthe American Revolu-
tion, she claimed, is the establishment offreedom, or really the
foundation of a political body that guarantees the space where
freedom can operate.7 Arendt puts the accent on the
establishment
ofthis democracy in society, that is, the fixity ofits foundation and
the stability ofits f
unctioning. The revolution succeeds in her
estimation to the extent that it puts an end to the dynamic of
constituent powers and establishes a stable constituted power.
Later we will critique this notion ofnetwork power contained
in the U.S. Constitution, but here we want simply to highlight its
originality. Against the modern European conceptions ofsover-
eignty, which consigned political power to a transcendent realm
and thus estranged and alienated the sources ofpower from society,
here the concept ofsovereignty refers to a power entirely within
society. Politics is not opposed to but integrates and completes so-
ciety.
Extensive Empire
Before moving on to analyze how in the course of U.S. history
this new principle ofsovereignty developed and was transformed,
let us concentrate our attention for a moment on the nature of
the concept itself. The first characteristic of the U.S. notion of
sovereignty is that it poses an idea ofthe immanence ofpower
in opposition to the transcendent character ofmodern European
sovereignty. This idea ofimmanence is based on an idea ofproduc-
tivity. Ifit were not, the principle would be impotent: in immanence
alone, nothing allows society to become political. The multitude
that constitutes society is productive. U.S. sovereignty does not
consist, then, in the regulation ofthe multitude but arises, rather,
as the result ofthe productive synergies ofthe multitude. The
humanist revolution ofthe Renaissance and the subsequent experi-
ences ofsectarian Protestantism all developed this idea ofproductiv-
ity. In line with the Protestant ethic, one might say that only the
N E T W O R K P O W E R : U . S . S O V E R E I G N T Y
165
productive power ofthe multitude demonstrates the existence of
God and the presence ofdivinity on earth.8 Power is not something
that lords over us but something that we make. The American
Declaration ofIndependence celebrates this new idea ofpower
in the clearest terms. The emancipation ofhumanity from every
transcendent power is grounded on the multitude’s power to con-
struct its own political institutions and constitute society.
This principle ofconstituent production, however, yields to
or is explained by a procedure ofself-reflection in a kind ofdialectical
ballet. This is the second characteristic ofthe U.S. notion ofsover-
eignty. In the process ofthe constitution ofsovereignty on the
plane ofimmanence, there also arises an experience offinitude that
results from the conflictive and plural nature of the multitude itself.
The new principle ofsovereignty seems to produce its own internal
limit. To prevent these obstacles from disrupting order and com-
pletely emptying out the project, sovereign power must rely on
the exercise ofcontrol. In other words, after the first moment of
affirmation comes a dialectical negation of the constituent power
ofthe multitude that preserves the teleology ofthe project of
sovereignty. Are we thus faced with a point of crisis in the elabora-
tion ofthe new concept? Does transcendence, first refused in the
definition ofthe source ofpower, return through the back door
in the exercise ofpower, when the multitude is posed as finite and
thus demanding special instruments ofcorrection and control?
That outcome is a constant threat, but after having recognized
these internal limits, the new U.S. concept ofsovereignty opens
with extraordinary force toward the outside, almost as if it wanted
to banish the idea ofcontrol and the moment ofreflection from
its own Constitution. The third characteristic ofthis notion of
sovereignty is its tendency toward an open, expansive project oper-
ating on an unbounded terrain. Although the text ofthe U.S. Con-
stitution is extremely attentive to the self-reflective moment, the
life and exercise of the Constitution are instead, throughout their
jurisprudential and political history, decidedly open to expansive
movements, to the renewed declaration ofthe democratic founda-
166
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
tion ofpower. The principle ofexpansion continually struggles
against the forces of limitation and control.9
It is striking how strongly this American experiment resembles
the ancient constitutional experience, and specifically the political
theory inspired by imperial Rome! In that tradition the conflict
between limit and expansion was always resolved in favor of expan-
sion. Machiavelli defined as expansive those republics whose demo-
cratic foundations led to both the continuous production of conflicts
and the appropriation ofnew territories. Polybius conceived expan-
siveness as the reward for the perfect synthesis of the three forms
ofgovernment, because the eminent form ofsuch a power encour-
ages the democratic pressure ofthe multitude to surpass every limit
and every control. Without expansion the republic constantly risks
being absorbed into the cycle ofcorruption.10
This democratic expansive tendency implicit in the notion of
network power must be distinguished from other, purely expansion-
ist and imperialist forms of expansion. The fundamental difference
is that the expansiveness ofthe immanent concept ofsovereignty
is inclusive, not exclusive. In other words, when it expands, this
new sovereignty does not annex or destroy the other powers it
faces but on the contrary opens itself to them, including them in
the network. What opens is the basis ofconsensus, and thus, through
the constitutive network ofpowers and counterpowers, the entire
sovereign body is continually reformed. Precisely because of this
expansive tendency, the new concept ofsovereignty is pro-
foundly reformist.11
We can now distinguish clearly the
expansive tendency
ofthe
democratic republic from the
expansionism
ofthe transcendent sovereigns—or from, because this is primarily what is at issue, the expan-
sionism ofmodern nation-states. The idea ofsovereignty as an
expansive power in networks is poised on the hinge that links the
principle ofa democratic republic to the idea ofEmpire. Empire
can only be conceived as a universal republic, a network ofpowers
and counterpowers structured in a boundless and inclusive architec-
ture. This imperial expansion has nothing to do with imperialism,
nor with those state organisms designed for conquest, pillage, geno-
N E T W O R K P O W E R : U . S . S O V E R E I G N T Y
167
cide, colonization, and slavery. Against such imperialisms, Empire
extends and consolidates the model ofnetwork power. Certainly,
when we consider these imperial processes historically (and we will
soon focus on them in U.S. history), we see clearly that the expansive
moments ofEmpire have been bathed in tears and blood, but
this ignoble history does not negate the difference between the
two concepts.
Perhaps the fundamental characteristic of imperial sovereignty
is that
its space is always open.
As we saw in earlier sections, the modern sovereignty that developed in Europe from the sixteenth
century onward conceived space as bounded, and its boundaries
were always policed by the sovereign administration. Modern sover-
eignty resides precisely on the limit. In the imperial conception,
by contrast, power finds the logics ofits order always renewed and
always re-created in expansion. This definition ofimperial power
raises numerous paradoxes: the indifference of the subjects coupled
with the singularization ofproductive networks; the open and ex-
pansive space ofEmpire together with its continuous reterritorializa-
tions; and so forth. The idea of an Empire that is also a democratic
republic, however, is formed precisely by linking and combining the
extreme terms ofthese paradoxes. The tension ofthese conceptual
paradoxes will run throughout the articulation and establishment
ofimperial sovereignty in practice.
Finally, we should note that an idea ofpeace is at the basis of
the development and expansion ofEmpire. This is an immanent
idea ofpeace that is dramatically opposed to the transcendent idea
ofpeace, that is, the peace that only the transcendent sovereign
can impose on a society whose nature is defined by war. Here, on
the contrary, nature is peace. Virgil gives us perhaps the highest
expression ofthis Roman peace: ‘‘The final age that the oracle
foretold has arrived; / The great order of the centuries is born
again.’’12
Open Frontiers
The realization ofthe imperial notion ofsovereignty was a long
process that developed through the different phases of U.S. constitu-
168
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
tional history. As a written document, ofcourse, the U.S. Constitu-
tion has remained more or less unchanged (except for a few ex-
tremely important amendments), but the Constitution should also
be understood as a material regime ofjuridical interpretation and
practice that is exercised not only by jurists and judges but also by
subjects throughout the society. This material, social constitution
has indeed changed radically since the founding of the republic.
U.S. constitutional history, in fact, should be divided into four
distinct phases or regimes.13 A first phase extends from the Declara-
tion ofIndependence to the Civil War and Reconstruction; a
second, extremely contradictory, phase corresponds to the Progres-