Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
The emergence ofthe various components ofthe New Left was
an enormous and powerful affirmation of the principle of constituent
power and the declaration ofthe reopening ofsocial spaces.
Beyond the Cold War
During the cold war, when the United States ambiguously adopted
the mantle ofimperialism, it subordinated the old imperialist powers
to its own regime. The cold war waged by the United States did
not defeat the socialist enemy, and perhaps that was never really
its primary goal. The Soviet Union collapsed under the burden of
its own internal contradictions. The cold war at the most produced
some ofthe conditions ofisolation that, reverberating within the
Soviet bloc itself, multiplied those explosive contradictions. The
most important effect of the cold war was to reorganize the lines
ofhegemony within the imperialist world, accelerating the decline
ofthe old powers and raising up the U.S. initiative ofthe constitu-
tion ofan imperial order. The United States would not have been
victorious at the end ofthe cold war had a new type ofhegemonic
initiative not already been prepared. This imperial project, a global
180
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
project ofnetwork power, defines the fourth phase or regime of
U.S. constitutional history.
In the waning years and wake ofthe cold war, the responsibility
ofexercising an international police power ‘ fell’’ squarely on the
shoulders ofthe United States. The GulfWar was the first time
the United States could exercise this power in its full form. Really,
the war was an operation ofrepression ofvery little interest from
the point ofview ofthe objectives, the regional interests, and
the political ideologies involved. We have seen many such wars
conducted directly by the United States and its allies. Iraq was
accused ofhaving broken international law, and it thus had to be
judged and punished. The importance ofthe GulfWar derives
rather from the fact that it presented the United States as the only
power able to manage international justice,
not as a function of its
own national motives but in the name of global right.
Certainly, many powers have falsely claimed to act in the universal interest before,
but this new role of the United States is different. Perhaps it is most
accurate to say that this claim to universality may also be false, but
it is false in a new way. The U.S. world police acts not in imperialist
interest but in imperial interest. In this sense the GulfWar did
indeed, as George Bush claimed, announce the birth ofa new
world order.
Legitimation ofthe imperial order, however, cannot be based
on the mere effectiveness of legal sanction and the military might
to impose it. It must be developed through the production of
international juridical norms that raise up the power ofthe hege-
monic actor in a durable and legal way. Here the constitutional
process that had originated with Wilson finally reaches maturity
and emerges again. Between the First and Second World Wars,
between Wilson’s messianism and the international economic-
political initiatives ofthe New Deal (which we will return to in
Section 3.2), a series ofinternational organizations was built that
produced what in the traditional contractual terms ofinternational
right is called a surplus ofnormativity and efficacy. This surplus
was given an expansive and tendentially universal basis in the spirit
N E T W O R K P O W E R : U . S . S O V E R E I G N T Y
181
ofthe San Francisco accords that founded the United Nations. The
unifying, internal process was hindered by the cold war, but not
completely blocked by it. Through the years ofthe cold war there
was both a multiplication ofinternational organisms capable of
producing right and a reduction ofthe resistances to their function-
ing. We emphasized in Section 1.1 how the proliferation of these
different international organisms and their consolidation in a set of
symbiotic relationships—as ifthe one asked the other for its own
legitimation—pushed beyond a conception ofinternational right
based in contract or negotiation, and alluded instead to a central
authority, a legitimate supranational motor ofjuridical action. The
objective process was thus given a subjective face. The great interna-
tional institutions, which had been born on the limited basis of
negotiations and pacts, led to a proliferation of organisms and actors
that began to act as ifthere were a central authority sanctioning right.
With the end ofthe cold war, the United States was called
to serve the role ofguaranteeing and adding juridical efficacy to
this complex process ofthe formation ofa new supranational right.
Just as in the first century ofthe Christian era the Roman senators
asked Augustus to assume imperial powers ofthe administration
for the public good, so too today the international organizations
(the United Nations, the international monetary organizations, and
even the humanitarian organizations) ask the United States to assume
the central role in a new world order. In all the regional conflicts
ofthe late twentieth century, from Haiti to the Persian Gulfand
Somalia to Bosnia, the United States is called to intervene mili-
tarily—and these calls are real and substantial, not merely publicity
stunts to quell U.S. public dissent. Even ifit were reluctant, the
U.S. military would have to answer the call in the name ofpeace
and order. This is perhaps one ofthe central characteristics of
Empire—that is, it resides in a world context that continually calls
it into existence. The United States is the peace police, but only
in the final instance, when the supranational organizations ofpeace
call for an organizational activity and an articulated complex of
juridical and organizational initiatives.
182
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
There are many reasons for the United States’ privileged posi-
tion in the new global constitution ofimperial authority. It can
be explained in part by the continuity ofthe United States’ role
(particularly its military role) from the central figure in the struggle
against the USSR to the central figure in the newly unified world
order. From the perspective ofthe constitutional history we are
tracing here, however, we can see that the United States is privileged
in a more important way by the imperial tendency ofits own
Constitution. The U.S. Constitution, as Jefferson said, is the one
best calibrated for extensive Empire. We should emphasize once
again that this Constitution is imperial and not imperialist. It is
imperial because (in contrast to imperialism’s project always to
spread its power linearly in closed spaces and invade, destroy, and
subsume subject countries within its sovereignty) the U.S. constitu-
tional project is constructed on the model ofrearticulating an open
space and reinventing incessantly diverse and singular relations in
networks across an unbounded terrain.
The contemporary idea ofEmpire is born through the global
expansion ofthe internal U.S. constitutional project. It is in fact
through the extension of
internal
constitutional processes that we enter into a constituent process ofEmpire. International right always
had to be a negotiated, contractual process among
external
par-
ties—in the ancient world that Thucydides portrayed in the Melian
Dialogue, in the era ofstate reason, and in the modern relations
among nations. Today right involves instead an internal and consti-
tutive institutional process. The networks ofagreements and associa-
tions, the channels ofmediation and conflict resolution, and the
coordination ofthe various dynamics ofstates are all institutionalized
within Empire. We are experiencing a first phase ofthe transforma-
tion ofthe global frontier into an open space ofimperial sovereignty.
2.6
I M P E R I A L S O V E R E I G N T Y
The new men ofEmpire are the ones who believe in fresh starts,
new chapters, new pages; I struggle on with the old story, hoping
that before it is finished it will reveal to me why it was that I
thought it worth the trouble.
J. M. Coetzee
There is a long tradition ofmodern critique dedicated
to denouncing the dualisms ofmodernity. The standpoint ofthat
critical tradition, however, is situated in the paradigmatic place of
modernity itself, both ‘‘inside’’ and ‘‘outside,’’ at the threshold or
the point ofcrisis. What has changed in the passage to the imperial
world, however, is that this border place no longer exists, and thus
the modern critical strategy tends no longer to be effective.
Consider, for example, the responses offered in the history of
modern European philosophy from Kant to Foucault to the question
‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’ Kant provides the classic modernist char-
acterization ofthe mandate ofthe Enlightenment:
Sapere aude
(dare
to know), emerge from the present state of ‘‘immaturity,’’ and
celebrate the public use ofreason at the center ofthe social realm.1
Foucault’s version, when we situate it historically, is not really all
that different. Foucault was dealing not with Fredrick II’s despotism,
which Kant wanted to guide toward more reasonable political posi-
tions, but rather with the political system ofthe French Fifth Repub-
lic, in which a large public sphere for political exchange was taken
for granted. His response nonetheless insists once again on the
necessity ofstraddling the border that links what traditionally would
184
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
be considered the ‘‘inside’’ ofsubjectivity and the ‘‘outside’’ ofthe
public sphere—even though in Foucault’s terms the division is
inverted so as to divide the ‘‘inside’’ ofthe system from the ‘‘outside’’
ofsubjectivity.2 The rationality ofmodern critique, its center of
gravity, is posed on this border.
Foucault does add another line ofinquiry that seeks to go
beyond these boundaries and the modern conception ofthe public
sphere. ‘‘What is at stake . .
. is this: How can the growth of
capabilities [
capaciteś
] be disconnected from the intensification of power relations?’’ And this new task requires a new method: ‘‘We
have to move beyond the outside-inside alternative.’’ Foucault’s
response, however, is quite traditional: ‘‘We have to be at the
frontiers.’’3 In the end, Foucault’s philosophical critique ofthe
Enlightenment returns to the same Enlightenment standpoint. In
this ebb and flow between inside and outside, the critique ofmoder-
nity does not finally go beyond its terms and limits, but rather
stands poised on its boundaries.
This same notion ofa border place that serves as the standpoint
for the critique ofthe system ofpower—a place that is both inside
and outside—also animates the critical tradition ofmodern political
theory. Modern republicanism has long been characterized by a
combination ofrealistic foundations and utopian initiatives. Repub-
lican projects are always solidly rooted within the dominant histori-
cal process, but they seek to transform the realm of politics that
thus creates an outside, a new space ofliberation. The three highest
examples ofthis critical tradition ofmodern political theory, in our
opinion, are Machiavelli, Spinoza, and Marx. Their thought is
always grounded within the real processes ofthe constitution of
modern sovereignty, attempting to make its contradictions explode
and open the space for an alternative society. The outside is con-
structed from within.
For Machiavelli, the constituent power that is to found a
democratic politics is born out ofthe rupture ofthe medieval order
and through the necessity ofregulating the chaotic transformations
ofmodernity. The new democratic principle is a utopian initiative
I M P E R I A L S O V E R E I G N T Y
185
that responds directly to the real historical process and the demands
ofthe epochal crisis. In Spinoza, too, the critique ofmodern sover-
eignty emerges from within the historical process. Against the de-
ployments ofmonarchy and aristocracy, which can only remain
limited forms, Spinoza defines democracy as the absolute form of
government because in democracy all ofsociety, the entire multi-
tude, rules; in fact, democracy is the only form of government in
which the absolute can be realized. For Marx, finally, every libera-
tory initiative, from wage struggles to political revolutions, proposes
the independence ofuse value against the world ofexchange value,
against the modalities ofcapitalist development—but that indepen-
dence exists only within capitalist development itself. In all these
cases the critique ofmodernity is situated
within
the historical evolution ofthe forms ofpower,
an inside that searches for an outside.
Even in the most radical and extreme forms of the call for an outside,
the inside is still assumed as foundation—albeit sometimes a negative