Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
developed not
imperial
but
imperialist
forms. The concept of Empire nonetheless survived in Europe, and its lack ofreality
was continually mourned. The European debates about Empire
and decline interest us for two primary reasons: first, because
the crisis ofthe ideal ofimperial Europe is at the center of
these debates, and second, because this crisis strikes precisely in
that secret place ofthe definition ofEmpire where the concept
ofdemocracy resides. Another element that we have to keep in
mind here is the standpoint from which the debates were
conducted: a standpoint that adopts the historical drama ofthe
decline ofEmpire in terms ofcollective lived experience. The
theme of
the crisis of Europe
was translated into a discourse on
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
375
the decline ofEmpire and linked to the crisis ofdemocracy,
along with the forms of consciousness and resistance that this
crisis implies.
Alexis de Tocqueville was perhaps the first to present the
problem in these terms. His analysis ofmass democracy in the
United States, with its spirit ofinitiative and expansion, led him
to the bitter and prophetic recognition ofthe impossibility f
or
European eĺites to continue to maintain a position ofcommand
over world civilization.3 Hegel had already perceived something
very similar: ‘‘America is . . . the country ofthe future, and its
world-historical importance has yet to be revealed in the ages which
lie ahead . . . It is a land ofdesire for all those who are weary
ofthe historical arsenal ofold Europe.’’4 Tocqueville, however,
understood this passage in a much more profound way. The reason
for the crisis of European civilization and its imperial practices
consists in the fact that European virtue—or really its aristocratic
morality organized in the institutions ofmodern sovereignty—
cannot manage to keep pace with the vital powers ofmass de-
mocracy.
The death ofGod that many Europeans began to perceive
was really a sign ofthe expiration oftheir own planetary centrality,
which they could understand only in terms ofa modern mysticism.
From Nietzsche to Burkhardt, from Thomas Mann to Max Weber,
from Spengler to Heidegger and Ortega y Gasset, and numerous
other authors who straddled the nineteenth and twentieth centuries,
this intuition became a constant refrain that was sung with such
bitterness!5 The appearance ofthe masses on the social and political
scene, the exhaustion ofthe cultural and productive models of
modernity, the waning ofthe European imperialist projects, and
the conflicts among nations on questions ofscarcity, poverty, and
class struggle: all these emerged as irreversible signs ofdecline.
Nihilism dominated the era because the times were without hope.
Nietzsche gave the definitive diagnosis: ‘‘Europe is sick.’’6 The two
World Wars that would ravage its territories, the triumph offascism,
and now, after the collapse of Stalinism, the reappearance of the
376
T H E D E C L I N E A N D F A L L O F E M P I R E
most terrible specters ofnationalism and intolerance all stand as
proofto confirm that these intuitions were in fact correct.
From our standpoint, however, the fact that against the old
powers ofEurope a new Empire has formed is only good news.
Who wants to see any more ofthat pallid and parasitic European
ruling class that led directly from the ancien re´gime to nationalism,
from populism to fascism, and now pushes for a generalized neolib-
eralism? Who wants to see more ofthose ideologies and those
bureaucratic apparatuses that have nourished and abetted the rotting
European eĺites? And who can still stand those systems oflabor
organization and those corporations that have stripped away every
vital spirit?
Our task here is not to lament the crisis ofEurope, but rather
to recognize in its analyses the elements that, while confirming its
tendency, still indicate possible resistances, the margins ofpositive
reaction, and the alternatives ofdestiny. These elements have often
appeared almost against the will ofthe theorists ofthe crisis oftheir
own times: it is a resistance that leaps to a future time—a real and
proper future past, a kind of future perfect tense. In this sense,
through the painful analyses ofits causes, the crisis ofEuropean
ideology can reveal the definition ofnew, open resources. This is
why it is important to follow the developments of the crisis of
Europe, because not only in authors such as Nietzsche and Weber
but also in the public opinion ofthe times, the denunciation of
the crisis revealed an extremely powerful positive side, which con-
tained the fundamental characteristics of the new world Empire we
are entering today. The agents ofthe crisis ofthe old imperial world
became foundations of the new. The undifferentiated mass that by
its simple presence was able to destroy the modern tradition and
its transcendent power appears now as a powerful productive force
and an uncontainable source ofvalorization. A new vitality, almost
like the barbaric forces that buried Rome, reanimates the field of
immanence that the death ofthe European God lef
t us as our
horizon. Every theory ofthe crisis ofEuropean Man and ofthe
decline ofthe idea ofEuropean Empire is in some way a symptom
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
377
of the new vital force of the masses, or as we prefer, of the desire
ofthe multitude. Nietzsche declared this from the mountaintops:
‘ I have absorbed in myselfthe spirit ofEurope—now I want to
strike back!’’7 Going beyond modernity means going beyond the
barriers and transcendences ofEurocentrism and leads toward the
definitive adoption ofthe field ofimmanence as the exclusive terrain
ofthe theory and practice ofpolitics.
In the years after the explosion of the First World War, those
who had participated in the great massacre tried desperately to
understand and control the crisis. Consider the testimonies ofFranz
Rosenzweig and Walter Benjamin. For both ofthem a kind of
secular eschatology was the mechanism by which the experience
ofthe crisis could be set free.8 After the historical experience of
war and misery, and also perhaps with an intuition ofthe holocaust
to come, they tried to discover a hope and a light ofredemption.
This attempt, however, did not succeed in escaping the powerful
undertow ofthe dialectic. Certainly the dialectic, that cursed dialec-
tic that had held together and anointed European values, had been
emptied out from within and was now defined in completely nega-
tive terms. The apocalyptic scene on which this mysticism searched
for liberation and redemption, however, was still too implicated in
the crisis. Benjamin recognized this bitterly: ‘‘The past carries with
it a temporal index by which it is referred to redemption. There
is a secret agreement between past generations and the present. Our
coming was expected on earth. Like every generation that preceded
us, we have been endowed with a
weak
Messianic power, a power
to which the past has a claim.’’9
This theoretical experience arose precisely where the crisis of
modernity appeared with the most intensity. On this same terrain
other authors sought to break with the remnants ofthe dialectic
and its powers ofsubsumption. It seems to us, however, that even
the strongest thinkers ofthe day were not able to break with the
dialectic and the crisis. In Max Weber the crisis ofsovereignty and
legitimacy can be resolved only through recourse to the irrational
figures ofcharisma. In Carl Schmitt the horizon ofsovereign prac-
378
T H E D E C L I N E A N D F A L L O F E M P I R E
tices can be cleared only by recourse to the ‘‘decision.’’ An irrational
dialectic, however, cannot resolve or even attenuate the crisis of
reality.10 And the powerful shadow of an aestheticized dialectic slips
even into Heidegger’s notion ofa pastoral function over a scattered
and fractured being.
For the real clarification ofthis scene, we are most indebted
to the series ofFrench philosophers who reread Nietzsche several
decades later, in the 1960s.11 Their rereading involved a reorienta-
tion ofthe standpoint ofthe critique, which came about when they
began to recognize the end ofthe functioning ofthe dialectic and
when this recognition was confirmed in the new practical, political
experiences that centered on the production ofsubjectivity. This
was a production ofsubjectivity as power, as the constitution ofan
autonomy that could not be reduced to any abstract or transcendent
synthesis.12 Not the dialectic but refusal, resistance, violence, and
the positive affirmation of being now marked the relationship be-
tween the location ofthe crisis in reality and the adequate response.
What in the midst ofthe crisis in the 1920s appeared as transcendence
against history, redemption against corruption, and messianism
against nihilism now was constructed as an ontologically definite
position outside and against, and thus beyond every possible resi-
due ofthe dialectic. This was a new materialism which negated
every transcendent element and constituted a radical reorientation
ofspirit.
In order to understand the profundity of this passage, one
would do well to focus on the awareness and anticipation of it in
the thought ofLudwig Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein’s early writings
gave a new life to the dominant themes of early twentieth-century
European thought: the condition ofdwelling in the desert ofsense
and searching for meaning, the coexistence of a mysticism of the
totality and the ontological tendency toward the production of
subjectivity. Contemporary history and its drama, which had been
stripped away from any dialectic, were then removed by Witt-
genstein from any contingency. History and experience became
the scene ofa materialist and tautological refoundation ofthe subject
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
379
in a desperate attempt to find coherence in the crisis. In the midst
ofWorld War I Wittgenstein wrote: ‘‘How things stand, is God.
God is, how things stand. Only from the consciousness of the
uniqueness of my life
arises religion—science—and art.’’ And further:
‘‘This consciousness is life itself. Can it be an ethics even if there
is no living being outside myself? Can there be any ethics if there
is no living being but myself? If ethics is supposed to be something
fundamental, there can. If I am right, then it is not sufficient for
the ethical judgment that a world be given. Then the world in
itselfis neither good nor evil . . . Good and evil only enter through
the
subject.
And the subject is not part ofthe world, but a boundary ofthe world.’’ Wittgenstein denounces the God ofwar and the
desert ofthings in which good and evil are now indistinguishable
by situating the world on the limit oftautological subjectivity:
‘‘Here one can see that solipsism coincides with pure realism, ifit
is strictly thought out.’’13 This limit, however, is creative. The
alternative is completely given when, and only when, subjectivity
is posed outside the world: ‘‘My propositions serve as elucidations
in the following way: anyone who understands me eventually recog-
nizes them as nonsensical, when he has used them—as steps—to
climb up beyond them. (He must, so to speak, throw away the ladder
after he has climbed up it.) He must transcend these propositions, and
then he will see the world aright.’’14 Wittgenstein recognizes the
end ofevery possible dialectic and any meaning that resides in the
logic ofthe world and not in its marginal, subjective surpassing.
The tragic trajectory ofthis philosophical experience allows
us to grasp those elements that made the perception ofthe crisis
ofmodernity and the decline ofthe idea ofEurope a (negative but
necessary) condition ofthe definition ofthe coming Empire. These
authors were voices crying out in the desert. Part ofthis generation
would be interned in extermination camps. Others would perpetu-
ate the crisis through an illusory faith in Soviet modernization.
Others still, a significant group ofthese authors, would flee to
America. They were indeed voices crying out in the desert, but
their rare and singular anticipations oflife in the desert give us the
380
T H E D E C L I N E A N D F A L L O F E M P I R E
means to reflect on the possibilities ofthe multitude in the new
reality ofpostmodern Empire. Those authors were the first to define
the condition ofthe complete deterritorialization ofthe coming
Empire, and they were situated in it just as the multitudes are
situated in it today. The negativity, the refusal to participate, the
discovery ofan emptiness that invests everything: this means situat-
ing oneselfperemptorily in an imperial reality that is itselfdefined