Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
is in this sense the central terrain ofanalysis. This problematic has
been posed by authors from Lukaćs to Benjamin, from Adorno to
the later Wittgenstein, from Foucault to Deleuze, and indeed by
nearly all those who have recognized the twilight ofmodernity. In
all ofthese cases the question was posed against such tremendous
metaphysical obstacles! And we can now see how pallid their re-
sponses were with respect to the enormity ofthe question. What
is certain today is that the problematic does not risk repeating the
old models ofthe metaphysical tradition, even the most powerful
ones. In fact, every metaphysical tradition is now completely worn
out. Ifthere is to be a solution to the problem, it cannot help being
material and explosive. Whereas our attention was first drawn to
the intensity ofthe elements ofvirtuality that constituted the multi-
tude, now it must focus on the hypothesis that those virtualities
accumulate and reach a threshold ofrealization adequate to their
power. This is the sense in which we speak ofgeneral intellect and
its articulations in knowledge, affect, and cooperation; and similarly
the sense in which we speak ofthe various forms ofthe collective
exodus ofthose nomadic movements ofthe multitude that appro-
priate spaces and renew them.
Here we are dealing with two passages. The first consists in
the fact that virtuality totalizes the field of the
res gestae.
Virtuality steps forward and demonstrates that the capacity of the
historia rerum
gestarum
to dominate the active virtual singularities has definitively expired. This is the
historia
that comes to an end when the new
virtualities emerge as powerful and liberate themselves from a being
that is invested hegemonically by capital and its institutions. Today
V I R T U A L I T I E S
369
only the
res gestae
are charged with historical capacities, or rather, today there is no history, only historicity. The second passage consists in the fact that these singular virtualities as they gain their
autonomy also become self-valorizing. They express themselves as
machines ofinnovation. They not only refuse to be dominated by
the old systems ofvalue and exploitation, but actually create their
own irreducible possibilities as well. Here is where a materialist
telos is defined, founded on the action of singularities, a teleology
that is a resultant ofthe
res gestae
and a figure ofthe machinic logic ofthe multitude.
The
res gestae,
the singular virtualities that operate the connec-
tion between the possible and the real, are in the first passage outside
measure and in the second beyond measure. Singular virtualities,
which are the hinge between possible and real, play both these
cards: being outside measure as a destructive weapon (deconstructive
in theory and subversive in practice); and being beyond measure
as constituent power. The virtual and the possible are wedded as
irreducible innovation and as a revolutionary machine.
4.2
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
You can not spill a drop ofAmerican blood without spilling the
blood ofthe whole world . . . [O]ur blood is as the flood ofthe
Amazon, made up ofa thousand noble currents all pouring into
one. We are not a nation, so much as a world; for unless we may
claim all the world for our sire, like Melchisedec, we are with-
out mother or father . . . Our ancestry is lost in the universal
paternity . . . We are the heirs ofall time, and with all nations
we divide our inheritance.
Herman Melville
Fate has willed it that America is from now on to be at the center
ofWestern civilization rather than on the periphery.
Walter Lippmann
There is no escaping American business.
Louis-Ferdinand Ceĺine
The theory ofthe constitution ofEmpire is also a theory
ofits decline, as European theorists ofEmpire have recognized for
the last several thousand years. Already in Greco-Roman antiquity,
Thucydides, Tacitus, and Polybius all recounted the sequence of
rise and fall, as did later the Fathers of the Church and the theorists
ofearly Christianity. In none ofthese cases when speaking ofEmpire
was it simply a matter for them of repeating the classical theory of the
alternation between ‘‘positive’’ and ‘‘negative’’ forms of government,
because Empire by definition goes beyond this alternation. The
internal crisis ofthe concept ofEmpire, however, became com-
pletely clear only in the Enlightenment period and the period of
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
371
the construction ofEuropean modernity, when authors such as
Montesquieu and Gibbon made the problem ofthe decadence of
the Roman Empire one ofthe central topoi ofthe analysis ofthe
political forms of the modern sovereign state.1
Riseand Fall (Machiavelli)
In classical antiquity the concept ofEmpire already presupposed
crisis. Empire was conceived in the framework of a naturalist theory
ofthe forms ofgovernment; and, even though it breaks the cyclical
alternation of good and bad forms, it is not exempt from the destiny
ofthe corruption ofthe city and civilization as a whole. History
is dominated by Thyche (Fortune or Destiny), which at times
inevitably ruins the perfection that Empire achieves. From Thucyd-
ides to Tacitus and from Athens to Rome, the necessary equilibrium
between the forms of common life and command was situated in
this linear destiny. Polybius’ analyses ofthe Roman Empire broke
with this conception ofthe cyclical character ofhistorical develop-
ment whereby the human construction ofthe political constantly
shifts from the good to the bad forms of the city and power:
from monarchy to tyranny, from aristocracy to oligarchy, and from
democracy to anarchy, and then eventually begins a new cycle.
Polybius claimed that the Roman Empire broke with this cycle by
creating a synthesis ofthe good forms ofpower (see Section 3.5).
Empire is thus understood not so much as rule over universal space
and time, but rather as a movement that gathers together the spaces
and the temporalities through the powers ofthe social forces that
seek to liberate themselves from the natural cyclical character of
the time ofhistory. Surpassing the line ofdestiny, however, is
aleatory. The synthesis ofthe good f
orms ofgovernment, the
government ofcivic virtue, can defy destiny but cannot replace
it. Crisis and decline are determinations that every day must be
overcome.
During the European Enlightenment, authors such as Montes-
quieu and Gibbon rejected the naturalist conception ofthis process.
The decline ofEmpire was explained in social scientific terms as a
372
T H E D E C L I N E A N D F A L L O F E M P I R E
result ofthe impossibility ofmaking last the historical and social
constructions ofthe multitude and the virtue ofits heroes. The
corruption and decline ofEmpire were thus not a natural presuppo-
sition, determined by the cyclical destiny ofhistory, but rather a
product ofthe human impossibility (or at least the extreme difficulty)
ofgoverning an unlimited space and time. The limitlessness of
Empire undermined the capacity to make the good institutions
function and last. Nonetheless, Empire was an end toward which
the desire and the civic virtue ofthe multitude and its human
capacities to make history all tended. It was a precarious situation
that could not support unbounded space and time, but instead
ineluctably limited the universal aims ofgovernment to finite politi-
cal and social dimensions. The Enlightenment authors told us that
the government that approximates perfection will be constructed
with moderation across limited space and time. Between Empire
and the reality ofcommand, therefore, there was a contradiction
in principle that would inevitably spawn crises.
Machiavelli, looking back at the conception ofthe ancients
and anticipating that of the moderns, is really the one who offers
us the most adequate illustration ofthe paradox ofEmpire.2 He
clarified the problematic by separating it from both the naturalizing
terrain ofthe ancients and the sociological terrain ofthe moderns,
presenting it, rather, on the field ofimmanence and pure politics.
In Machiavelli, expansive government is pushed forward by the
dialectic ofthe social and political forces ofthe Republic. Only
where the social classes and their political expressions are posed in
an open and continuous play ofcounterpower are freedom and
expansion linked together, and hence only there does Empire be-
come possible. There is no concept ofEmpire, Machiavelli says,
that is not a decisively expansive concept offreedom. Precisely in
this dialectic offreedom, then, is where the elements ofcorruption
and destruction reside. When Machiavelli discusses the fall of the
Roman Empire, he focuses first and foremost on the crisis of civil
religion, or really on the decline ofthe social relation that had
unified the different ideological social forces and allowed them
to participate together in the open interaction ofcounterpowers.
G E N E R A T I O N A N D C O R R U P T I O N
373
Christian religion is what destroyed the Roman Empire by destroy-
ing the civic passion that pagan society had sustained, the conflictual
but loyal participation ofthe citizens in the continuous perfecting
ofthe constitution and the process offreedom.
The ancient notion ofthe necessary and natural corruption
ofthe good forms ofgovernment is thus radically displaced because
they can be evaluated only in relation to the social and political
relationship that organized the constitution. The Enlightenment
and modern notion ofthe crisis ofunbounded and uncontrollable
space and time is similarly displaced because it too was led back to
the realm ofcivic power: on this and no other basis can space and
time be evaluated. The alternative is thus not between government
and corruption, or between Empire and decline, but between on
the one hand socially rooted and expansive government, that is,
‘‘civic’’ and ‘‘democratic’’ government, and on the other every
practice ofgovernment that grounds its own power on transcen-
dence and repression. We should be clear here that when we speak
ofthe ‘‘city’’ or ‘‘democracy’’ in quotation marks as the basis for
the expansive activity ofthe Republic, and as the only possibility
for a lasting Empire, we are introducing a concept of participation
that is linked to the vitality ofa population and to its capacity to
generate a dialectic ofcounterpowers—a concept, therefore, that
has little to do with the classical or the modern concept ofdemoc-
racy. Even the reigns ofGenghis Khan and Tamerlane were from
this perspective somewhat ‘‘democratic,’’ as were Caesar’s legions,
Napoleon’s armies, and the armies ofStalin and Eisenhower, since
each ofthem enabled the participation ofa population that supported
its expansive action. What is central in all ofthese cases, and in the
general concept ofEmpire, is that a terrain ofimmanence be af-
firmed. Immanence is defined as the absence ofevery external limit
from the trajectories ofthe action ofthe multitude, and immanence
is tied only, in its affirmations and destructions, to regimes of possi-
bility that constitute its formation and development.
Here we find ourselves back at the center ofthe paradox by
which every theory ofEmpire conceives the possibility ofits own
decline—but now we can begin to explain it. IfEmpire is always
374
T H E D E C L I N E A N D F A L L O F E M P I R E
an absolute positivity, the realization ofa government ofthe multi-
tude, and an absolutely immanent apparatus, then it is exposed to
crisis precisely on the terrain ofthis definition, and not for any
other necessity or transcendence opposed to it. Crisis is the sign of
an alternative possibility on the plane ofimmanence—a crisis that
is not necessary but always possible. Machiavelli helps us understand
this immanent, constitutive, and ontological sense ofcrisis. Only
in the present situation, however, does this coexistence ofcrisis
and the field ofimmanence become completely clear. Since the
spatial and temporal dimensions ofpolitical action are no longer
the limits but the constructive mechanisms ofimperial government,
the coexistence ofthe positive and the negative on the terrain of
immanence is now configured as an open alternative. Today the
same movements and tendencies constitute both the rise and the
decline ofEmpire.
Finis Europae(Wittgenstein)
The coexistence ofthe imperial spirit with signs ofcrisis and
decline has appeared in many different guises in European dis-
course over the past two centuries, often as a reflection either
on the end ofEuropean hegemony or on the crisis ofdemocracy
and the triumph ofmass society. We have insisted at length
throughout this book that the modern governments ofEurope